Jump to content

Francisco Suárez: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
→‎Works: Added the list of main works
Line 74: Line 74:
In 1613, at the instigation of [[Pope Paul V]], Suárez wrote a treatise dedicated to the Christian princes of Europe, entitled ''Defensio catholicae fidei contra anglicanae sectae errores'' ("Defense of the Universal Catholic Faith Against the Errors of the Anglican Sect").<ref>[http://www.archive.org/stream/americanecclesia57cathuoft#page/512/mode/2up Jollain, Japeth S.] ''"Francis Suarez: The Man and His History,"'' The Ecclesiastical Review, Vol. LVII, 1917.</ref> This was directed against the [[Oath of Allegiance (1606)|oath of allegiance]] which [[James I of England|James I]] required from his subjects. James (himself a talented scholar) caused it to be burned by the common hangman, and forbade its perusal under the 'severest penalties, complaining bitterly to [[Philip III of Spain|Philip III]] that he should harbour in his dominions a declared enemy of the throne and majesty of kings.
In 1613, at the instigation of [[Pope Paul V]], Suárez wrote a treatise dedicated to the Christian princes of Europe, entitled ''Defensio catholicae fidei contra anglicanae sectae errores'' ("Defense of the Universal Catholic Faith Against the Errors of the Anglican Sect").<ref>[http://www.archive.org/stream/americanecclesia57cathuoft#page/512/mode/2up Jollain, Japeth S.] ''"Francis Suarez: The Man and His History,"'' The Ecclesiastical Review, Vol. LVII, 1917.</ref> This was directed against the [[Oath of Allegiance (1606)|oath of allegiance]] which [[James I of England|James I]] required from his subjects. James (himself a talented scholar) caused it to be burned by the common hangman, and forbade its perusal under the 'severest penalties, complaining bitterly to [[Philip III of Spain|Philip III]] that he should harbour in his dominions a declared enemy of the throne and majesty of kings.


== Works ==
== Main Works ==

From 1597 to 1636 the ''Disputationes Metaphysicae'' were published in seventeen editions. In the 18th century, the Venice edition of ''Opera Omnia'' in 23 volumes in folio (1740–1751) appeared, followed by the Parisian Vivès edition, 28 volumes (1856–1861); in 1965 the Vivés edition of the ''Disputationes Metaphysicae'' (volls. 25-26) was reprinted by Georg Olms, Hildesheim. No modern edition of Suárez's complete works is yet available. Only few of Suárez's ''Disputations'' have been translated into English.
* ''De Incarnatione'' (1590-1592)
* ''De sacramentis'' (1593-1603)
* ''Disputationes metaphysicae'' (1597)
* ''De divina substantia eiusque attributis'' (1606)
* ''De divina praedestinatione et reprobatione'' (1606)
* ''De sanctissimo Trinitatis mysterio'' (1606)
* ''De religione'' (1608-1625)
* ''De legibus'' (1612)
* ''De gratia'' (1619)
* ''De angelis'' (1620)
* ''De opere sex dierum'' 1621)
* ''De anima'' (1621)
* ''De fide, spe et charitate'' (1622)
* ''De ultimo fine hominis'' (1628)

In the 18th century, the Venice edition of ''Opera Omnia'' in 23 volumes in folio (1740–1751) appeared, followed by the Parisian Vivès edition, 26 volumes + 2 volumes of indices (1856–1861); in 1965 the Vivés edition of the ''Disputationes Metaphysicae'' (volls. 25-26) was reprinted by Georg Olms, Hildesheim.
From 1597 to 1636 the ''Disputationes Metaphysicae'' were published in seventeen editions; no modern edition of Suárez's complete works is yet available and only few of Suárez's ''Disputations'' have been translated into English.


== Influence ==
== Influence ==

Revision as of 08:27, 10 August 2013

Francisco Suárez
Born(1548-01-05)January 5, 1548
DiedSeptember 25, 1617(1617-09-25) (aged 69)
EraModern philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolScholasticism
Monument in Granada, Spain, where he was born

Francisco Suárez (5 January 1548 – 25 September 1617) was a Spanish Jesuit priest, philosopher and theologian, one of the leading figures of the School of Salamanca movement, and generally regarded among the greatest scholastics after Thomas Aquinas.

Life and career

Francisco Suárez was born in Granada, Andalusia (southern Spain).

At age sixteen Suárez entered the Society of Jesus in Salamanca, and he studied Philosophy and Theology there for five years from 1565 to 1570. It seems he was not a promising student at first; in fact, he nearly gave up his matters of study after failing the entrance exam twice. After passing the exam at third attempt, though, things changed, and he completed his course of Philosophy with distinction, going on to study Theology, to then teach Philosophy in Ávila and Segovia. He was ordained in 1572, and taught Theology in Ávila, Segovia (1575), Valladolid (1576), Rome (1580–85), Alcalá (1585–92), Salamanca (1592–97), and Coimbra (1597–1616).

He wrote on a wide variety of subjects, producing a vast amount of work (his complete works in Latin amount to twenty-six volumes). Suárez writings include treatises on law, the relationship between Church and State, metaphysics, and theology. He is considered the godfather of International Law. His Disputationes metaphysicae were widely read in Europe during the 17th century and are considered by some scholars to be his most profound work.

Suárez was regarded during his lifetime as being the greatest living philosopher and theologian, and given the nickname Doctor Eximius et Pius ("Exceptional and Pious Doctor"); Pope Gregory XIII attended his first lecture in Rome. Pope Paul V invited him to refute the errors of James I of England, and wished to retain him near his person, to profit by his knowledge. Philip II of Spain sent him to the University of Coimbra in order to give it prestige, and when Suárez visited the University of Barcelona, the doctors of the university went out to meet him wearing the insignia of their faculties.

After his death in Portugal (in either Lisbon or Coimbra) his reputation grew still greater, and he had a direct influence on such leading philosophers as Hugo Grotius, René Descartes, John Norris, and Gottfried Leibniz.

In 1679 Pope Innocent XI publicly condemned sixty-five casuist propositions, taken chiefly from the writings of Escobar, Suárez and others, mostly Jesuit, theologians as propositiones laxorum moralistarum and forbade anyone to teach them under penalty of excommunication.[1]

Philosophical thought

His most important philosophical achievements were in metaphysics and the philosophy of law. Suárez may be considered the last eminent representative of mediaeval scholasticism. He adhered to a moderate form of Thomism and developed metaphysics as a systematic enquiry.

Metaphysics

For Suárez, metaphysics was the science of real essences (and existence); it was mostly concerned with real being rather than conceptual being, and with immaterial rather than with material being. He held (along with earlier scholastics) that essence and existence are the same in the case of God (see ontological argument), but disagreed with Aquinas and others that the essence and existence of finite beings are really distinct. He argued that in fact they are merely conceptually distinct: rather than being really separable, they can only logically be conceived as separate.

On the vexed subject of universals, he endeavored to steer a middle course between the realism of Duns Scotus and the nominalism of William of Occam. His position is a little bit closer to nominalism than that of Thomas Aquinas.[2] Sometimes he is classified as a moderate nominalist, but his admitting of objective precision (praecisio obiectiva) ranks him with moderate realists. The only veritable and real unity in the world of existences is the individual; to assert that the universal exists separately ex parte rei would be to reduce individuals to mere accidents of one indivisible form. Suárez maintains that, though the humanity of Socrates does not differ from that of Plato, yet they do not constitute realiter one and the same humanity; there are as many "formal unities" (in this case, humanities) as there are individuals, and these individuals do not constitute a factual, but only an essential or ideal unity ("In such a way, that many individuals, which are said to be of the same nature, are so: only through the operation of the intellect, not through a substance or essence of things which unites them").[3] The formal unity, however, is not an arbitrary creation of the mind, but exists "in the nature of the thing, prior [ontologically] to any operation of the intellect".[4]

His metaphysical work, giving a remarkable effort of systematisation, is a real history of medieval thought, combining the three schools available at that time: Thomism, Scotism and Nominalism. He is also a deep commentator of Arabic or high medieval works. He enjoyed the reputation of being the greatest metaphysician of his time. He thus founded a school of his own, Suarezianism, the chief characteristic principles of which are:

  • the principle of individuation by the proper concrete entity of beings
  • the rejection of pure potentiality of matter
  • the singular as the object of direct intellectual cognition
  • a distinctio rationis ratiocinatae between the essence and the existence of created beings
  • the possibility of spiritual substance only numerically distinct from one another
  • ambition for the hypostatic union as the sin of the fallen angels
  • the Incarnation of the Word, even if Adam had not sinned
  • the solemnity of the vow only in ecclesiastical law
  • the system of Congruism that modifies Molinism by the introduction of subjective circumstances, as well as of place and of time, propitious to the action of efficacious grace, and with predestination ante praevisa merita
  • the possibility of holding one and the same truth by both science and faith
  • the belief in Divine authority contained in an act of faith
  • the production of the body and blood of Christ by transubstantiation as constituting the Eucharistic sacrifice
  • the final grace of the Blessed Virgin Mary superior to that of the angels and saints combined.[5]

Suárez made an important classification of being in Disputationes Metaphysicae (1597), which influenced the further development of theology within Catholicism (his fellow Jesuit Pedro da Fonseca having a powerful effect on Protestant Scholastic thought in the 16th and 17th centuries). In the second part of the book, disputations 28-53, Suárez fixes the distinction between ens infinitum (God) and ens finitum (created beings). The first division of being is that between ens infinitum and ens finitum. Instead of dividing being into infinite and finite, it can also be divided into ens a se and ens ab alio, i.e., being that is from itself and being that is from another. A second distinction corresponding to this one:ens necessarium and ens contingens, i.e., necessary being and contingent being. Still another formulation of the distinction is between ens per essentiam and ens per participationem, i.e., being that exists by reason of its essence and being that exists only by participation in a being that exists on its own (eigentlich). A further distinction is between ens increatum and ens creatum, i.e., uncreated being and created, or creaturely, being. A final distinction is between being as actus purus and being as ens potentiale, i.e., being as pure actuality and being as potential being. Suárez decided in favor of the first classification of the being into ens infinitum and ens finitum as the most fundamental, in connection with which he accords the other classifications their due.

Theology

In theology, Suárez attached himself to the doctrine of Luis Molina, the celebrated Jesuit professor of Évora. Molina tried to reconcile the doctrine of predestination with the freedom of the human will and the predestinarian teachings of the Dominicans by saying that the predestination is consequent upon God's foreknowledge of the free determination of man's will, which is therefore in no way affected by the fact of such predestination. Suárez endeavoured to reconcile this view with the more orthodox doctrines of the efficacy of grace and special election, maintaining that, though all share in an absolutely sufficient grace, there is granted to the elect a grace which is so adapted to their peculiar dispositions and circumstances that they infallibly, though at the same time quite freely, yield themselves to its influence. This mediatizing system was known by the name of "congruism."

Philosophy of law

Here Suárez' main importance stems probably from his work on natural law, and from his arguments concerning positive law and the status of a monarch. In his extensive work Tractatus de legibus ac deo legislatore (reprinted, London, 1679) he is to some extent the precursor of Grotius and Samuel Pufendorf, in making an important distinction between natural law and international law, which he saw as based on custom. Though his method is throughout scholastic, he covers the same ground, and Grotius speaks of him in terms of high respect. The fundamental position of the work is that all legislative as well as all paternal power is derived from God, and that the authority of every law resolves itself into His. Suárez refutes the patriarchal theory of government and the divine right of kings founded upon it---doctrines popular at that time in England and to some extent on the Continent. He argued against the sort of social-contract theory that became dominant among early-modern political philosophers such as Thomas Hobbes and John Locke, but some of his thinking found echoes in the more liberal, Lockean contract theorists.

Human beings, argued Suárez, have a social nature bestowed upon them by God, and this includes the potential to make laws. But when a political society is formed, the authority of the state is not of divine but of human origin; therefore, its nature is chosen by the people involved, and their natural legislative power is given to the ruler.[6] Because they gave this power, they have the right to take it back, to revolt against a ruler — but only if the ruler behaves badly towards them, and they're obliged to act moderately and justly. In particular, the people must refrain from killing the ruler, no matter how tyrannical he may have become. If a government is imposed on people, on the other hand, they not only have the right to defend themselves by revolting against it, they are entitled to kill the tyrannical ruler.

In 1613, at the instigation of Pope Paul V, Suárez wrote a treatise dedicated to the Christian princes of Europe, entitled Defensio catholicae fidei contra anglicanae sectae errores ("Defense of the Universal Catholic Faith Against the Errors of the Anglican Sect").[7] This was directed against the oath of allegiance which James I required from his subjects. James (himself a talented scholar) caused it to be burned by the common hangman, and forbade its perusal under the 'severest penalties, complaining bitterly to Philip III that he should harbour in his dominions a declared enemy of the throne and majesty of kings.

Main Works

  • De Incarnatione (1590-1592)
  • De sacramentis (1593-1603)
  • Disputationes metaphysicae (1597)
  • De divina substantia eiusque attributis (1606)
  • De divina praedestinatione et reprobatione (1606)
  • De sanctissimo Trinitatis mysterio (1606)
  • De religione (1608-1625)
  • De legibus (1612)
  • De gratia (1619)
  • De angelis (1620)
  • De opere sex dierum 1621)
  • De anima (1621)
  • De fide, spe et charitate (1622)
  • De ultimo fine hominis (1628)

In the 18th century, the Venice edition of Opera Omnia in 23 volumes in folio (1740–1751) appeared, followed by the Parisian Vivès edition, 26 volumes + 2 volumes of indices (1856–1861); in 1965 the Vivés edition of the Disputationes Metaphysicae (volls. 25-26) was reprinted by Georg Olms, Hildesheim. From 1597 to 1636 the Disputationes Metaphysicae were published in seventeen editions; no modern edition of Suárez's complete works is yet available and only few of Suárez's Disputations have been translated into English.

Influence

The contributions of Suarez to metaphysics and theology exerted significant influence over 18th century scholastic theology among both Roman Catholics and Protestants.[8]

Among early Protestant scholastics the influence of his Disputationes Metaphysicae is evident in the writings of Bartholomaeus Keckermann (1571–1609), Clemens Timpler (1563–1624), Gilbertus Jacchaeus (1578–1628), Johann Heinrich Alsted (1588–1638), Antonius Walaeus (1573–1639), and Johannes Maccovius (Jan Makowski; 1588–1644), among others.[9] This influence was so pervasive that by 1643 it provoked the Dutch Reformed theologian Jacobus Revius to publish his book-length response: Suarez repurgatus.[10]

See also

Bibliography

  • Aho, Tuomo, Suárez on Cognitive Intentions, in: Paul.J.J.M. Bakker and Johannes M.M.H. Thijssen, (eds.), Mind, Cognition and Representation. The Tradition of Commentaries on Aristotle's De anima, Ashgate Studies in Medieval Philosophy, 2007, pp. 179–203.
  • Castellote, Salvador, Die Anthropologie des Suárez (Symposion 8) Karl Alber Verlag, Freiburg/München 2. Ed. 1982, 207 pp.
  • Castellote, Salvador, Die Kategorienlehre des Suárez: Relatio, actio, passio. Mit einer Einleitung über die Grundzüge seines metaphysischen Systems", Aeme Edizioni, Verona (It), 2011, 233 pp.
  • Doyle John P. Collected Studies on Francisco Suárez S.J. (1548–1617), edited by Victor M. Salas, Leuven, Leuven University Press, 2010.
  • Fichter, Joseph H. Man of Spain: Francis Suarez. New York: Macmillan, 1940.
  • Gracia, Jorge J. E. "Suárez on Individuation: Metaphysical Disputation V, Individual Unity and Its Principle," (Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press, 2000).
  • Hill, Benjamin & Lagerlund Henrik, (eds.) The Philosophy of Francisco Suarez New York: Oxford University Press 2012.
  • Marschler, Thomas, Die spekulative Trinitätslehre des Francisco Suárez SJ in ihrem philosophisch-theologischen Kontext (BGPhMA NF 71), Münster: Aschendorff 2007
  • Renemann, Michael, Gedanken als Wirkursachen. Francisco Suárez zur geistigen Hervorbringung, B. R. Grüner, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, 2010, 173 pp.
  • Ross, James F. "Translator's Introduction", in On Formal and Universal Unity: De Unitate Formali et Universali by Francis Suarez,(Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1964), pp. 1–27.
  • Sgarbi, Marco (ed.), Francisco Suárez and his Legacy. The Impact of Suárezian Metaphysics and Epistemology on Modern Philosophy, Vita e Pensiero, Milano, 2010, 294 pp.
  • Smith, Gerard (ed). Jesuit Thinkers of the Renaissance. Milwaukee, 1939, pp. 1–62.
  • Wroblewski, Pawel P. Arystotelesowska nauka o nieskonczonosci w metafizycznej reinterpretacji Francisco Suareza. Zarys problematyki / Aristotelian doctrine of the Infinity in the metaphysical reinterpretation of Francisco Suarez. An Outline of Issues, in: Krzysztof Rzepkowski (ed.), Aemulatio & Imitatio. Powrot pisarzy starozytnych w epoce renesansu / Aemulatio & Imitatio. The Return of the Ancient Writers in the epoque of the Renaissance, Warszawa: Instytut Filologii Klasycznej Uniwersytetu Warszawskiego (Warsaw: Institute of Classical Philology, University of Warsaw), 2009, pp. 87–100.

References

  1. ^ Kelly, J.N.D., The Oxford History of the Popes, Oxford University Press, 1986. ISBN 0-19-282085-0
  2. ^ See the translation of Suárez's De Unitate Formali et Universali James Francis Ross (Translator) On Formal and Universal Unity: De Unitate Formali et Universali by Francis Suarez,(Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1964)
  3. ^ Original Latin: "ita ut plura individua, quae dicuntur esse ejusdem naturae, non sint unum quid vera entitate quae sit in rebus, sed solum fundamentaliter vel per intellectum"
  4. ^ Original Latin: "in natura rei ante omnem operationem intellectus."
  5. ^ Pérez Goyena, Antonio. "Francisco Suárez". The Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company, 1912. Retrieved September 20, 2012.
  6. ^ http://www.acton.org - Francisco Suarez (1548 - 1617) - The Acton Institute - Microsoft Internet Explorer
  7. ^ Jollain, Japeth S. "Francis Suarez: The Man and His History," The Ecclesiastical Review, Vol. LVII, 1917.
  8. ^ Donnelly, John Patrick, Calvinism and Scholasticism in Vermigli's Doctrine of Man and Grace, Leiden: Brill, 1976, pp. 193-194.
  9. ^ Muller, Richard, Post-Reformation Reformed Dogmatics: The Rise and Development of Reformed Orthodoxy, ca. 1520 to ca. 1725, Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2003, volume 3, passim.
  10. ^ Revius, Jacobus, Suarez repurgatus, sive, Syllabus Disputationum metaphysicarum Francisci Suarez Societatis Iesu theologi, Lugduni Batavorum, 1644.

Template:Persondata