Jump to content

Philosophy: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Reverted to detailed history of (western) philosophy
Line 27: Line 27:
Many philosophical debates that began in ancient times are still debated today. [[Colin McGinn]] and others claim that no [[philosophical progress]] has occurred during that interval.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Problems in Philosophy: The Limits of Inquiry|last=McGinn|first=Colin|date=8 December 1993|url={{google books |plainurl=y |id=o_xMMPWzIecC}}|publisher=Wiley-Blackwell|isbn=978-1-55786-475-8|edition=1st}}</ref> [[David Chalmers|Chalmers]] and others, by contrast, see progress in philosophy similar to that in science,<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.sms.cam.ac.uk/media/1484158|title=Video & Audio: Why isn't there more progress in philosophy? – Metadata|website=www.sms.cam.ac.uk|access-date=25 April 2016}}</ref> while Talbot Brewer argued that "progress" is the wrong standard by which to judge philosophical activity.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The Retrieval of Ethics|last=Brewer|first=Talbot|date=11 June 2011|url={{google books |plainurl=y |id=d15rGnw_6rUC}}|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-969222-4|edition=1st|location=Oxford; New York}}</ref>
Many philosophical debates that began in ancient times are still debated today. [[Colin McGinn]] and others claim that no [[philosophical progress]] has occurred during that interval.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Problems in Philosophy: The Limits of Inquiry|last=McGinn|first=Colin|date=8 December 1993|url={{google books |plainurl=y |id=o_xMMPWzIecC}}|publisher=Wiley-Blackwell|isbn=978-1-55786-475-8|edition=1st}}</ref> [[David Chalmers|Chalmers]] and others, by contrast, see progress in philosophy similar to that in science,<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.sms.cam.ac.uk/media/1484158|title=Video & Audio: Why isn't there more progress in philosophy? – Metadata|website=www.sms.cam.ac.uk|access-date=25 April 2016}}</ref> while Talbot Brewer argued that "progress" is the wrong standard by which to judge philosophical activity.<ref>{{Cite book|title=The Retrieval of Ethics|last=Brewer|first=Talbot|date=11 June 2011|url={{google books |plainurl=y |id=d15rGnw_6rUC}}|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-969222-4|edition=1st|location=Oxford; New York}}</ref>


== Philosophy and Culture ==
== {{anchor|History}}Historical overview ==
In one sense, philosophy is synonymous with wisdom or learning. In that sense, all cultures have a philosophical tradition.
In one general sense, philosophy is associated with wisdom, intellectual culture and a search for knowledge. In that sense, all cultures and literate societies ask philosophical questions such as "how are we to live" and "what is the nature of reality". A broad and impartial conception of philosophy then, finds a reasoned inquiry into such matters as reality, morality and life in all world civilizations.<ref>Garfield (Editor), Edelglass (Editor); The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy, Introduction.</ref>
; Western philosophy

===Western philosophy===
{{Main article|Western philosophy}}
{{Main article|Western philosophy}}
[[File:Socrates Pio-Clementino Inv314.jpg|right|thumb|150px|Bust of Socrates in the [[Vatican Museum]]]]

[[Western philosophy]] is the philosophical tradition of the [[Western world]] and dates to [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|Pre-Socratic]] thinkers who were active in [[Ancient Greece]] in the 6th century BC such as [[Thales]] (c. 624 – c. 546 BC) and [[Pythagoras]] (c. 570 – c. 495 BC) who practiced a "love of wisdom" (''philosophia'')<ref name=":02">{{Cite book|url={{google books |plainurl=y |id=b_VvghYDArwC}}|title=Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Greek philosophy|last=Hegel|first=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich|last2=Brown|first2=Robert F.|date=1 January 2006|publisher=Clarendon Press|isbn=978-0-19-927906-7|page=33}}</ref> and were also termed ''physiologoi'' (students of ''physis'', or nature). [[Socrates]] was a very influential philosopher, who insisted that he possessed no ''wisdom'' but was a ''pursuer of'' wisdom.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0174%3Atext%3DSym.%3Asection%3D201d|title=Plato's "Symposium"|website=www.perseus.tufts.edu|page=201d and following.|access-date=22 April 2016}}</ref> [[Western philosophy]] can be divided into three eras: [[Ancient Greek philosophy|Ancient]] (Greco-Roman), [[Medieval philosophy]] (Christian European), and [[Modern philosophy]].

The Ancient era was dominated by [[Ancient Greek philosophy|Greek philosophical schools]] which arose out of the various pupils of Socrates, such as [[Plato]] who founded the [[Platonic Academy]], and was one of the most influential Greek thinkers for the whole of Western thought.<ref name="process"/> Plato's student [[Aristotle]] was also extremely influential, founding the [[Peripatetic school]]. Other traditions include [[Cynicism (philosophy)|Cynicism]], [[Stoicism]], [[Skepticism#Philosophical skepticism|Greek Skepticism]] and [[Epicureanism]]. Important topics covered by the Greeks included [[metaphysics]] (with competing theories such as [[atomism]] and [[monism]]), [[cosmology]], the nature of the well-lived life ([[eudaimonia]]), the possibility of knowledge and the nature of reason ([[logos]]). With the rise of the [[Roman empire]], Greek philosophy was also increasingly discussed in [[Latin language|Latin]] by [[Romans]] such as [[Cicero]] and [[Seneca the Younger|Seneca]].

[[Medieval philosophy]] (5th – 16th century) is the period following the fall of the Roman empire and was dominated by the rise of [[Christianity]] and hence reflects [[Judeo-Christian]] theological concerns as well as retaining a continuity with Greco-Roman thought. Problems such as the existence and nature of [[God]], the nature of [[faith]] and reason, metaphysics, the [[problem of evil]] were discussed in this period. Some key Medieval thinkers include [[St. Augustine]], [[Thomas Aquinas]], [[Boethius]], [[Anselm of Laon|Anselm]] and [[Roger Bacon]].. Philosophy for these thinkers was viewed as an aid to [[Theology]] (''ancilla theologiae'') and hence they sought to align their philosophy with their interpretation of sacred scripture. This period saw the development of [[Scholasticism]], a text critical method developed in [[medieval universities]] based on close reading and disputation on key texts. The [[Renaissance]] (1355–1650) period saw increasing focus on classic Greco-Roman thought and on a robust [[Humanism]].
[[File:Kant Portrait.jpg|thumb|200px|[[Immanuel Kant]].]]
[[Early modern philosophy]] in the Western world begins with thinkers such as [[Thomas Hobbes]] and [[René Descartes]] (1596–1650).<ref name="diane">{{cite book|title=Fifty Major Philosophers, A Reference Guide|page=125|author=Diane Collinson}}</ref> Following the rise of natural science, [[Modern philosophy]] was concerned with developing a secular and rational foundation for knowledge and moved away from traditional structures of authority such as religion, scholastic thought and the Church. Major modern philosophers include [[Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[David Hume|Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]].<ref name="philosophical12">Rutherford, ''The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'', p. 1: "Most often this [period] has been associated with the achievements of a handful of great thinkers: the so-called 'rationalists' (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz) and 'empiricists' (Locke, Berkeley, Hume), whose inquiries culminate in Kant's 'Critical philosophy.' These canonical figures have been celebrated for the depth and rigor of their treatments of perennial philosophical questions..."</ref><ref name="traditional">Nadler, ''A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'', p. 2: "The study of early modern philosophy demands that we pay attention to a wide variety of questions and an expansive pantheon of thinkers: the traditional canonical figures (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume), to be sure, but also a large 'supporting cast'..."</ref><ref name="philosophical13">[[Bruce Kuklick]], "Seven Thinkers and How They Grew: Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz; Locke, Berkeley, Hume; Kant" in Rorty, Schneewind, and Skinner (eds.), ''Philosophy in History'' (Cambridge University Press, 1984), p. 125: "Literary, philosophical, and historical studies often rely on a notion of what is ''canonical''. In American philosophy scholars go from Jonathan Edwards to John Dewey; in American literature from James Fenimore Cooper to F. Scott Fitzgerald; in political theory from Plato to Hobbes and Locke […] The texts or authors who fill in the blanks from A to Z in these, and other intellectual traditions, constitute the canon, and there is an accompanying narrative that links text to text or author to author, a 'history of' American literature, economic thought, and so on. The most conventional of such histories are embodied in university courses and the textbooks that accompany them. This essay examines one such course, the History of Modern Philosophy, and the texts that helped to create it. If a philosopher in the United States were asked why the seven people in my title comprise Modern Philosophy, the initial response would be: they were the best, and there are historical and philosophical connections among them."</ref> [[19th-century philosophy]] is influenced by the wider movement termed [[the Enlightenment]], and includes figures such as [[Hegel]] a key figure in [[German idealism]], [[Nietzsche]] a famed anti-Christian, [[J.S. Mill]] who promoted [[Utilitarianism]], [[Karl Marx]] who developed the foundations for [[Communism]] and the American [[William James]]. The 20th century saw the split between [[Analytic philosophy]] and [[Continental philosophy]], as well as philosophical trends such as [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|Phenomenology]], [[Existentialism]], [[Logical Positivism]], [[Pragmatism]] and the [[Linguistic turn]].

===Middle Eastern philosophy===
[[File:Zarathushtra.jpg|right|thumb|150px|Zoroaster]]
[[File:Avicenna Portrait on Silver Vase - Museum at BuAli Sina (Avicenna) Mausoleum - Hamadan - Western Iran (7423560860).jpg|right|thumb|150px|Avicenna Portrait on Silver Vase, Iran]]

{{See also|Islamic philosophy|Iranian philosophy}}
The regions of the [[fertile Crescent]], [[Iran]] and [[Arabia]] are home to the earliest known philosophical [[Wisdom literature]] and is today mostly dominated by [[Islamic culture]]. Early wisdom literature from the fertile crescent was a genre which sought to instruct people on ethical action, practical living and virtue through stories and proverbs. In [[Ancient Egypt]], these texts were known as [[sebayt]] ('teachings') and they are central to our understandings of [[Ancient Egyptian philosophy]]. [[Babylonian astronomy]] also included much philosophical speculations about cosmology which may have influenced the Ancient Greeks. [[Jewish philosophy]] and [[Christian philosophy]] are religio-philosophical traditions that developed both in the Middle East and in Europe, they both share certain early Judaic texts (mainly the [[Tanakh]]) and monotheistic beliefs. Jewish thinkers such as the [[Geonim]] of the [[Talmudic Academies in Babylonia]] and [[Maimonides]] engaged with Greek and Islamic philosophy. Later Jewish philosophy came under strong Western intellectual influences and includes the works of [[Moses Mendelssohn]] who ushered in the [[Haskalah]] (the Jewish Enlightenment), [[Jewish existentialism]] and [[Reform Judaism]].

Pre-Islamic [[Iranian philosophy]] begins with the work of [[Zoroaster]], one of the first promoters of [[monotheism]] and of the [[dualism]] between good and evil. This dualistic cosmogony influenced later Iranian developments such as [[Manichaeism]], [[Mazdakism]], and [[Zurvanism]].

After the [[Muslim conquests]], [[Early Islamic philosophy]] developed the Greek philosophical traditions in new innovative directions. This [[Islamic Golden Age]] influenced European intellectual developments. The two main currents of early Islamic thought are [[Kalam]] which focuses on [[Islamic theology]] and [[#Falsafa|Falsafa]] which was based on [[Aristotelianism]] and [[Neoplatonism]]. The work of Aristotle was very influential among the falsafa such as [[al-Kindi]] (9th century), [[Avicenna]] (980 – June 1037) and [[Averroes]] (12th century). Others such as [[Al-Ghazali]] were highly critical of the methods of the Aristotelian falsafa. Islamic thinkers also developed a [[scientific method]], experimental medicine, a theory of optics and a legal philosophy. [[Ibn Khaldun]] was an influential thinker in [[philosophy of history]].

In [[History of Iran|Iran]] several schools of Islamic philosophy continued to flourish after the Golden Age and includes currents such as the [[Illuminationist philosophy]] of [[Mulla Sadra]], [[Sufi philosophy]], and [[Transcendent theosophy]]. The 19th and 20th century [[Arab world]] saw the [[Al-Nahda|Nahda]] (awakening or renaissance) movement which influenced [[contemporary Islamic philosophy]].


[[Western philosophy]] dates to the Greek philosophers, who were active in [[Ancient Greece]] beginning in the 6th century BC. [[Pythagoras]] distinguished himself from other "wise ones" by calling himself a mere ''lover of wisdom'', suggesting that he was not wise.<ref name=":02">{{Cite book|url={{google books |plainurl=y |id=b_VvghYDArwC}}|title=Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Greek philosophy|last=Hegel|first=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich|last2=Brown|first2=Robert F.|date=1 January 2006|publisher=Clarendon Press|isbn=978-0-19-927906-7|page=33}}</ref> [[Socrates]] used this title and insisted that he possessed no ''wisdom'' but was a ''pursuer of'' wisdom.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0174%3Atext%3DSym.%3Asection%3D201d|title=Plato's "Symposium"|website=www.perseus.tufts.edu|page=201d and following.|access-date=22 April 2016}}</ref> Socrates' student [[Plato]] is often credited as the founder of Western philosophy. The philosopher [[Alfred North Whitehead]] said of Plato: "The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato. I do not mean the systematic scheme of thought which scholars have doubtfully extracted from his writings. I allude to the wealth of general ideas scattered through them."<ref name="process" />
===Indian philosophy===
[[File:Long view nalanda.JPG|right|thumb|200px|[[Nalanda]] university]]
[[File:Photograph_of_Sarvepalli_Radhakrishnan_presented_to_First_Lady_Jacqueline_Kennedy_in_1962.jpg|right|thumb|200px|[[Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan]], philosopher and second president of India, 1962 to 1967.]]
{{See also|Eastern philosophy}}{{Main article|Indian philosophy}}
[[Indian philosophy]] ({{lang-sa|{{IAST|''darśana''}}}}; 'world views', 'teachings')<ref>[http://spokensanskrit.de/index.php?tinput=darzana&direction=SE&script=HK&link=yes&beginning=0 Soken Sanskrit, ''darzana'']</ref> are philosophical traditions originating in the [[Indian subcontinent]]. Traditions of Indian philosophy are generally classified as either orthodox or heterodox – [[Āstika and nāstika|āstika or nāstika]] – depending on whether they accept the authority of the [[Vedas]] and whether they accept the theories of [[Brahman]] and [[Atman (Hinduism)|Atman]].<ref>John Bowker, ''Oxford Dictionary of World Religions'', p. 259</ref><ref>{{cite book|author=Wendy Doniger |title=On Hinduism |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=c8vRAgAAQBAJ |year=2014|publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-936008-6|page=46}}</ref> The orthodox schools generally include [[Nyaya]], [[Vaisheshika]], [[Samkhya]], [[Yoga (philosophy)|Yoga]], [[Mīmāṃsā]] and [[Vedanta]], and the common heterodox schools are [[Jainism|Jain]], [[Buddhism|Buddhist]], [[Ajivika]] and [[Cārvāka]]. Some of the earliest surviving philosophical texts are the [[Upanishads]] of the [[Vedic period#Later Vedic period (1000–500 BCE)|later Vedic period (1000–500 BCE)]]. Important Indian philosophical concepts include [[dharma]], [[karma]], [[samsara]], [[moksha]] and [[ahimsa]]. Indian philosophers developed a system of epistemological reasoning ([[pramana]]) and logic and investigated topics such as metaphysics, ethics, [[hermeneutics]] and [[soteriology]]. Indian philosophy also covered topics such as political philosophy as seen in the [[Arthashastra]] c. 4th century BCE and the philosophy of love as seen in the [[Kama Sutra]].


; Eastern philosophy
The commonly named six orthodox schools arose sometime between the start of the [[Common Era]] and the [[Gupta Empire]].<ref>Students' Britannica India (2000), Volume 4, Encyclopædia Britannica, ISBN 978-0852297605, page 316</ref> These Hindu schools developed what has been called the "Hindu synthesis" merging orthodox [[Brahmanical]] and unorthodox elements from Buddhism and Jainism as a way to respond to the unorthodox challenges.<ref>Hiltebeitel, Alf (2007), Hinduism. In: Joseph Kitagawa, "The Religious Traditions of Asia: Religion, History, and Culture", Routledge</ref> Hindu thought also spread east to the Indonesian [[Srivijaya empire]] and the Cambodian [[Khmer Empire]].
{{Main article|Eastern philosophy}}
[[File:Zarathushtra.jpg|right|thumb|150px|The Iranian prophet [[Zarathustra]] is credited as the founder of [[Zoroastrianism]].]]
Eastern philosophy is a term that encompasses the many philosophical currents originating outside Europe, including [[China]], [[India]], [[Japan]], [[Persian Empire|Persia]] and other regions. They have their own timelines, regions and philosophers. Major traditions include:


* [[African philosophy]] and [[Ethiopian philosophy]]
Later developments include the development of [[Tantra]] and Iranian-Islamic influences. Buddhism mostly disappeared from India after the [[Muslim conquest in the Indian subcontinent]], surviving in the Himalayan regions and south India.<ref>{{cite book|author=Randall COLLINS|title=THE SOCIOLOGY OF PHILOSOPHIES|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2HS1DOZ35EgC |year=2009|publisher=Harvard University Press|isbn=978-0-674-02977-4 |pages=184–185}}</ref> The modern era saw the rise of [[Hindu nationalism]], [[Hindu reform movements]] and [[Neo-Vedanta]] (or Hindu modernism) whose major proponents included [[Vivekananda]], [[Mahatma Gandhi]] and [[Aurobindo]] and who for the first time promoted the idea of a unified "[[Hinduism]]". Due to the influence of British colonialism, much modern Indian philosophical work was in English and includes thinkers such as [[Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan|Radhakrishnan]], [[Krishna Chandra Bhattacharya]] and [[M. Hiriyanna]].<ref>Garfield (Editor), Edelglass (Editor); The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy, Anglophone philosophy in Colonial India.</ref>
* [[Ancient Egyptian philosophy]] and [[Babylonian literature#Philosophy|Babylonian literature]]

* [[Indian philosophy]], [[Jain philosophy]] and [[Hindu philosophy]]
===Buddhist philosophy===
{{Main article|Buddhist philosophy|Buddhist ethics}}
* [[Iranian philosophy]]
* East Asian [[Neo-Confucianism]] and [[Buddhist philosophy]], [[Japanese philosophy]] and [[Korean philosophy]]
[[File:Monks debating at Sera monastery, 2013.webm|thumb|Monks debating at [[Sera monastery]], Tibet, 2013.]]
* Persian [[Zoroastrianism]]
[[Buddhist philosophy]] begins with the thought of [[Gautama Buddha]] (fl. between sixth and fourth centuries BCE) and is preserved in the [[Buddhist texts#Texts of the Early schools|early Buddhist texts]]. Buddhist thought is trans-regional and trans-cultural. It originated in India and later spread to [[East Asia]], [[Tibet]], [[Central Asia]], and [[Southeast Asia]], developing new and syncretic traditions in these different regions. The various Buddhist schools of thought are the dominant philosophical tradition in [[Tibet]] and Southeast Asian countries like [[Sri Lanka]] and [[Burma]]. Because [[Avidyā (Buddhism)|ignorance]] to the true nature of things is considered one of the roots of suffering ([[dukkha]]), Buddhist philosophy is concerned with epistemology, metaphysics, ethics and psychology. The ending of [[dukkha]] also encompasses [[Buddhist meditation|meditative practices]]. Key innovative concepts include the [[Four Noble Truths]], [[Anatta]] (not-self) a critique of a fixed [[personal identity]], the transience of all things ([[Anicca]]), and a certain [[The unanswered questions|skepticism about metaphysical questions]].
* Middle Eastern [[Islamic philosophy]]

* European [[Jewish philosophy]] and [[Christian philosophy]]
Later Buddhist philosophical traditions developed a complex phenomenological psychology termed [[Abhidharma]]. [[Mahayana]] philosophers such as [[Nagarjuna]] and [[Vasubandhu]] developed the theories of [[Shunyata]] (emptiness of all phenomena) and Vijnapti-matra (appearance only), a form of phenomenology or [[transcendental idealism]]. The [[Dignāga]] school of [[Pramāṇa]] promoted a complex form of [[epistemology]] and [[Buddhist logic]]. After the disappearance of Buddhism from India, these philosophical traditions continued to develop in the [[Tibetan Buddhist]], [[East Asian Buddhist]] and [[Theravada Buddhist]] traditions. The modern period saw the rise of [[Buddhist modernism]] and [[Humanistic Buddhism]] under Western influences and the development of a [[Buddhism in the West|Western Buddhism]] with influences from modern psychology and Western philosophy.
* Mesoamerican [[Aztec philosophy]]

===East Asian philosophy===
{{Main article|Chinese philosophy|Korean philosophy|Japanese philosophy}}
[[File:Rongo Analects 02.jpg|thumb|The [[Analects]] of [[Confucius]] (fl. 551–479 BCE)]]
[[File:Kitaro Nishidain in Feb. 1943.jpg|thumb|170px|Kitarō Nishida, professor of philosophy at Kyoto University and founder of the [[Kyoto School]].]]
East Asian philosophical thought began in [[History of China#Ancient China|Ancient China]], and [[Chinese philosophy]] begins during the [[Western Zhou]] Dynasty and the following periods after its fall when the "[[Hundred Schools of Thought]]" flourished (6th century to 221 BC).<ref>Garfield (Editor), Edelglass (Editor); The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy, Chinese philosophy.</ref><ref name="pe">{{cite book|last= Ebrey |first=Patricia|year=2010 |page= 42|title=The Cambridge Illustrated History of China|publisher=Cambridge University Press}}</ref> This period was characterized by significant intellectual and cultural developments and saw the rise of the major philosophical schools of China, [[Confucianism]], [[Legalism (Chinese philosophy)|Legalism]], and [[Daoism]] as well as numerous other less influential schools. These philosophical traditions developed metaphysical, political and ethical theories such [[Tao]], [[Yin and yang]], [[Ren (Confucianism)|Ren]] and [[Li (Confucianism)|Li]] which, along with [[Chinese Buddhism]], directly influenced [[Korean philosophy]], [[Vietnamese philosophy]] and [[Japanese philosophy]] (which also includes the native [[Shinto]] tradition). Buddhism began arriving in China during the [[Han Dynasty]] (206 BCE–220 CE), through a [[Silk Road transmission of Buddhism|gradual Silk road transmission]] and through native influences developed distinct Chinese forms (such as Chan/[[Zen]]) which spread throughout the [[East Asian cultural sphere]]. During later Chinese dynasties like the [[Ming Dynasty]] (1368–1644) as well as in the Korean [[Joseon dynasty]] (1392–1897) a resurgent [[Neo-Confucianism]] became the dominant school of thought, and was promoted by the state.

In the Modern era, Chinese thinkers incorporated ideas from Western philosophy. [[Chinese Marxist philosophy]] developed under the influence of [[Mao Zedong]], a Chinese pragmatism under [[Hu Shih]] and [[New Confucianism]]'s rise was influenced by [[Xiong Shili]]. Modern Japanese thought meanwhile developed under strong Western influences such as the study of Western Sciences ([[Rangaku]]) and the modernist [[Meirokusha]] intellectual society which drew from European enlightenment thought. The 20th century saw the rise of [[State Shinto]] and also [[Statism in Shōwa Japan|Japanese nationalism]]. The [[Kyoto School]], an influential and unique Japanese philosophical school developed from Western phenomenology and Medieval Japanese Buddhist philosophy such as that of [[Dogen]].

===African philosophy===
[[File:Frantz Fanon.jpg|thumb|200px|[[Frantz Fanon]].]]
[[African philosophy]] is philosophy produced by [[African people]], philosophy that presents African worldviews, ideas and themes, or philosophy that uses distinct African philosophical methods. Modern African thought has been occupied with [[Ethnophilosophy]], with defining the very meaning of African philosophy and its unique characteristics and what it means to be [[African people|African]].<ref>Bruce B. Janz, Philosophy in an African Place (2009), pp. 74–79, Plymouth, UK: Lexington Books, https://books.google.com/books?isbn=0739136682</ref> During the 17th century, [[Ethiopian philosophy]] developed a robust literary tradition as exemplified by [[Zera Yacob (philosopher)|Zera Yacob]]. Another early African philosopher was [[Anton Wilhelm Amo]] (c. 1703 – c. 1759) who became a respected philosopher in Germany. Distinct African philosophical ideas include [[Ujamaa]], the Bantu idea of [[Bantu Philosophy|'Force']], [[Négritude]], [[Pan-Africanism]] and [[Ubuntu (philosophy)|Ubuntu]]. Contemporary African thought has also seen the development of Professional philosophy and of [[Africana philosophy]], the philosophical literature of the [[African diaspora]] which includes currents such as [[black existentialism]] by [[African-Americans]]. Modern African thinkers have been influenced by [[Marxism]], [[African-American literature]], [[Critical theory]], [[Critical race theory]], [[Postcolonialism]] and [[Feminism]].

===Indigenous American philosophy===
[[File:Sun stone detail.JPG|thumb|The Aztec [[Aztec calendar stone|Sun Stone]], also known as the Aztec Calendar Stone, at [[National Museum of Anthropology]], [[Mexico City]].]]
[[Indigenous American philosophy]] is the philosophy of the [[Indigenous people of the Americas]]. There is a wide variety of beliefs and traditions among these different American cultures. Among some of the [[Native Americans in the United States]] there is a belief is a metaphysical principle called the "Great Mystery" ([[Siouan]]: [[Wakan Tanka]], [[Algonquian languages|Algonquian]]: [[Gitche Manitou]]). Another widely shared concept was that of [[Orenda]] or "spiritual power". According to Peter M. Whiteley, for the Native Americans, "Mind is critically informed by transcendental experience (dreams, visions and so on) as well as by reason."<ref name="rep.routledge.com">Whiteley; Native American philosophy, https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/native-american-philosophy/v-1</ref> The practices to access these transcendental experiences are termed [[Shamanism]]. Another feature of the indigenous American worldviews was their extension of ethics to non-human animals and plants.<ref name="rep.routledge.com"/><ref>Pierotti,Raymond; Communities as both Ecological and Social entities in Native American thought, http://www.se.edu/nas/files/2013/03/5thNAScommunities.pdf</ref>

In [[Mesoamerica]], [[Aztec philosophy]] was an intellectual tradition developed by individuals called [[Tlamatini]] ('those who know something') <ref>{{cite web |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=OI9J7R-R1awC&q=120#v=onepage&q=Tlamatini&f=false |title=Use of "Tlamatini" in ''Aztec Thought and Culture: A Study of the Ancient Nahuatl Mind – Miguel León Portilla'' |publisher=[[Google Books]] |accessdate=December 12, 2014}}</ref> and its ideas are preserved in various [[Aztec codices]]. The Aztec worldview posited the concept of an ultimate universal energy or force called [[Ometeotl]] which can be translated as "Dual Cosmic Energy" and sought a way to live in balance with a constantly changing, "slippery" world. The theory of Teotl can be seen as a form of [[Pantheism]].<ref name="iep.utm.edu">IEP, Aztec Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/aztec/</ref> Aztec philosophers developed theories of metaphysics, epistemology, values, and aesthetics. Aztec ethics was focused on seeking ''tlamatiliztli'' (knowledge, wisdom) which was based on moderation and balance in all actions as in the Nahua proverb "the middle good is necessary".<ref name="iep.utm.edu"/>

The [[Inca civilization]] also had an elite class of philosopher-scholars termed the Amawtakuna who were important in the [[Inca education]] system as teachers of religion, tradition, history and ethics.


== Categories ==
== Categories ==
Line 177: Line 134:


=== History of philosophy ===
=== History of philosophy ===
{{See also|History of ethics}}
{{further information|Philosophical progress|List of years in philosophy}}
Some philosophers specialize in one or more historical periods. The history of philosophy (study of a specific period, individual or school) is related to but not the same as the [[philosophy of history]] (the theoretical aspect of history, which deals with questions such as the nature of historical evidence and the possibility of objectivity).
Some philosophers specialize in one or more historical periods. The history of philosophy (study of a specific period, individual or school) is related to but not the same as the [[philosophy of history]] (the theoretical aspect of history, which deals with questions such as the nature of historical evidence and the possibility of objectivity).


Hegel's ''[[Lectures on the Philosophy of History]]'' influenced many philosophers to interpret truth in light of history, a view called [[historicism]].
Hegel's ''[[Lectures on the Philosophy of History]]'' influenced many philosophers to interpret truth in light of history, a view called [[historicism]].


==History==
=== Philosophical schools ===
{{Main|History of Western Philosophy}}
Some philosophers specialize in one or more of the major philosophical schools, such as [[Continental philosophy]], [[Analytical philosophy]], [[Thomism]], [[Asian philosophy]] or [[African philosophy]].
{{See also|Western philosophy|Eastern philosophy|History of ethics}}
{{further|Philosophical progress|List of years in philosophy}}
{{redirect|History of Western Philosophy|the book by Bertrand Russell|A History of Western Philosophy}}

[[Western philosophy]] has a long history dating back to the time of Socrates. It is conventionally divided into three large eras: ancient, medieval, and modern. Philosophy in the 20th century to present is considered "Contemporary philosophy". The history of philosophy is a rich field of study. This article does not aim for comprehensive detail but for a brief introduction to each period, with relevant links to other articles. The three historical periods are divided roughly as follows:

* Ancient (from 585 BC-400 AD)
* Medieval (400 - 1500)
* Modern (1500 - 1900)

=== Ancient ===
{{Main article|Hellenistic philosophy|Ancient Greek philosophy}}

[[File:Sanzio_01_Plato_Aristotle.jpg|thumb|[[Plato]] (''left'') and [[Aristotle]] (''right''): detail from ''[[The School of Athens]]'' by [[Raffaello Sanzio]], 1509]]

; [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|Pre-Socratic period]]
[[File:Turkey_ancient_region_map_ionia.JPG|right|thumb|200x200px|[[Ionia]], source of early Greek philosophy, in western [[Asia Minor]]]]
Ancient philosophers first articulated questions about the "arche" (the cause or first principle) of the [[universe]]. Western Philosophy is generally said to begin in the Greek cities of western Asia Minor (Ionia) with [[Thales]] of [[Miletus]], who was active around 585 B.C. and was responsible for the opaque dictum, "all is water." His most noted students were respectively [[Anaximander]] (all is [[Apeiron (cosmology)|apeiron]] (roughly, ''the unlimited'')) and [[Anaximenes of Miletus]] ("all is air"). [[Pythagoras]], from the island of Samos off the coast of Ionia, later lived at Croton in southern Italy (Magna Graecia). [[Pythagoreanism|Pythagoreans]] hold that "all is number," giving ''formal'' accounts in contrast to the previous ''material'' of the Ionians. They also believe in [[metempsychosis]], the transmigration of souls, or reincarnation.

;Socrates
[[File:Socrates_Pio-Clementino_Inv314.jpg|thumb|241x241px|Bust of Socrates]]
The key figure in Greek philosophy is [[Socrates]]. Socrates studied under several Sophists but transformed Greek philosophy into a unified and continuous project that is still pursued today. It is said that following a visit to the [[Oracle of Delphi]] he spent much of his life questioning anyone in Athens who would engage him, in order to disprove the oracular prophecy that there would be no man wiser than Socrates. Socrates used a critical approach called the "[[Socratic method|elenchus]]" or Socratic method to examine people's views. He aimed to study human things: the good life, justice, beauty, and virtue. Although Socrates wrote nothing himself, some of his many disciples wrote down his conversations. He was tried for corrupting the youth and impiety by the Greek democracy. He was found guilty and sentenced to death. Although his friends offered to help him escape from prison, he chose to remain in Athens and abide by his principles. His execution consisting in drinking the poison hemlock and he died in 399 B.C.

'''[[Plato]]'''

Socrates' most important student was Plato. Plato founded the [[Academy]] of Athens and wrote a number of dialogues, which applied the [[Socratic method]] of inquiry to examine philosophical problems. Some central ideas of Plato's dialogues are the immortality of the soul, the benefits of being just, that evil is ignorance, and the [[The Forms|Theory of Forms]]. Forms are universal properties that constitute true reality and contrast with the changeable material things he called "becoming".

; ''Aristotle''
Plato's most outstanding student was [[Aristotle]]. Aristotle was perhaps the first truly systematic philosopher and scientist. He wrote books on physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, aesthetics, poetry, theater, music, rhetoric, politics and logic. [[Aristotelian logic]] was the first type of [[logic]] to attempt to categorize every valid [[syllogism]]. Aristotle tutored Alexander the Great. Aristotelian philosophy exercised considerable influence on almost all western philosophers, including Greek, Roman, Christian, Jewish, and Islamic thinkers.
; The [[Neoplatonic]] and [[Christian]] philosophers of [[Late Antiquity]].

=== Medieval ===
{{Main article|Medieval philosophy}}

;Early and late medieval philosophy

Medieval philosophy is the philosophy of [[Western Europe]] and the [[Middle East]] during the [[Middle Ages]], roughly extending from the Christianization of the [[Roman Empire]] until the Renaissance.<ref name="encyclopedia" /> Medieval philosophy is defined partly by the rediscovery and further development of classical [[Greek philosophy|Greek]] and [[Hellenistic philosophy]], and partly by the need to address theological problems and to integrate the then widespread sacred doctrines of [[Abrahamic religion]] ([[Islam]], [[Judaism]], and [[Christianity]]) with [[Secularism|secular]] learning. Early medieval philosophy was influenced by the likes of [[Stoicism]], [[neo-Platonism]], but, above all, the philosophy of [[Plato]] himself.

Some problems discussed throughout this period are the relation of [[faith]] to [[reason]], the existence and unity of [[God]], the object of [[theology]] and [[metaphysics]], the problems of knowledge, of universals, and of individuation. The prominent figure of this period was St. Augustine who adopted Plato's thought and Christianized it in the 4th century and whose influence dominated medieval philosophy perhaps up to end of the era but was checked with the arrival of Aristotle's texts. Augustinianism was the preferred starting point for most philosophers (including the great [[St. Anselm of Canterbury]]) up until the 13th century.

[[File:St-thomas-aquinas.jpg|left|thumb|300x300px|St. [[Thomas Aquinas]]]]
Thomas Aquinas, the father of [[Thomism]], was immensely influential in Catholic Europe; he placed a great emphasis on reason and argumentation, and was one of the first to use the new translation of Aristotle's metaphysical and epistemological writing.

Philosophers from the Middle Ages include the Christian philosophers [[Augustine of Hippo]], [[Boethius]], [[Anselm of Canterbury|Anselm]], [[Gilbert of Poitiers]], [[Peter Abelard]], [[Roger Bacon]], [[Bonaventure]], [[Thomas Aquinas]], [[Duns Scotus]], [[William of Ockham]] and [[Jean Buridan]]; the Jewish philosophers [[Maimonides]] and [[Gersonides]]; and the [[Muslim]] philosophers [[Al-Kindi|Alkindus]], [[Al-Farabi|Alfarabi]], [[Ibn al-Haytham|Alhazen]], [[Avicenna]], [[Al-Ghazali|Algazel]], [[Ibn Bajjah|Avempace]], [[Ibn Tufail|Abubacer]], [[Ibn Khaldūn]], and [[Averroes]]. The medieval tradition of [[Scholasticism]] continued to flourish as late as the 17th century, in figures such as [[Francisco Suarez]] and [[John of St. Thomas]].

; Late Medieval and Renaissance
{{Main article|Renaissance philosophy}}

[[File:Giordano_Bruno_Campo_dei_Fiori.jpg|thumb|[[Giordano Bruno]]]]
The Renaissance ("rebirth") was a period of transition between the Middle Ages and modern thought,<ref name="contemporaries" /> in which the recovery of classical texts helped shift philosophical interests away from technical studies in logic, metaphysics, and theology towards eclectic inquiries into morality, philology, and mysticism.<ref name="philosophies">Frederick Copleston, ''A History of Philosophy, Volume III: From Ockham to Suarez'' (The Newman Press, 1953) p. 18: "When one looks at Renaissance philosophy … one is faced at first sight with a rather bewildering assortment of philosophies."</ref><ref name="renaissance3">Brian Copenhaver and Charles Schmitt, ''Renaissance Philosophy'' (Oxford University Press, 1992), p. 4: "one may identify the hallmark of Renaissance philosophy as an accelerated and enlarged interest, stimulated by newly available texts, in primary sources of Greek and Roman thought that were previously unknown or partially known or little read."</ref> The study of the classics and the humane arts generally, such as history and literature, enjoyed a scholarly interest hitherto unknown in Christendom, a tendency referred to as [[humanism]].<ref name="transmission" /><ref name="naturalistic">Copleston, ''ibid.'': "The bulk of Renaissance thinkers, scholars and scientists were, of course, Christians … but none the less the classical revival … helped to bring to the fore a conception of autonomous man or an idea of the development of the human personality, which, though generally Christian, was more 'naturalistic' and less ascetic than the mediaeval conception."</ref> Displacing the medieval interest in metaphysics and logic, the humanists followed [[Petrarch]] in making man and his virtues the focus of philosophy.<ref name="intellectual" /><ref name="The Renaissance Philosophy of Man" />

=== Modern ===
{{Main article|Modern philosophy}}

The term "modern philosophy" has multiple usages. For example, [[Thomas Hobbes]] is sometimes considered the first modern philosopher because he applied a systematic method to political philosophy.<ref name="Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy11" /><ref name="Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy" /> By contrast, [[René Descartes]] is often considered the first modern philosopher because he grounded his philosophy in problems of ''knowledge'', rather than problems of metaphysics.<ref name="diane">{{cite book|title=Fifty Major Philosophers, A Reference Guide|page=125|author=Diane Collinson}}</ref>

[[File:Frans_Hals_-_Portret_van_René_Descartes.jpg|thumb|171x171px|René Descartes]]Modern philosophy and especially [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] philosophy<ref name="philosophers" /> is distinguished by its increasing independence from traditional authorities such as the Church, academia, and Aristotelianism;<ref name="philosophical8">Steven Nadler, ''A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'', pp. 1–2: "By the seventeenth century […] it had become more common to find original philosophical minds working outside the strictures of the university—i.e., ecclesiastic—framework. […] by the end of the eighteenth century, [philosophy] was a secular enterprise."</ref><ref name="approaching">[[Anthony Kenny]], ''A New History of Western Philosophy'', vol. 3 (Oxford University Press, 2006), p. xii: "To someone approaching the early modern period of philosophy from an ancient and medieval background the most striking feature of the age is the absence of Aristotle from the philosophic scene."</ref> a new focus on the foundations of knowledge and metaphysical system-building;<ref name="epistemology">Donald Rutherford, ''The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'' (Cambridge University Press, 2006), p. 1: "epistemology assumes a new significance in the early modern period as philosophers strive to define the conditions and limits of human knowledge."</ref><ref name="metaphysical">Kenny, ''A New History of Western Philosophy'', vol. 3, p. 211: "The period between Descartes and Hegel was the great age of metaphysical system-building."</ref> and the emergence of modern physics out of natural philosophy.<ref name="independently">Kenny, ''A New History of Western Philosophy'', vol. 3, pp. 179–180: "the seventeenth century saw the gradual separation of the old discipline of natural philosophy into the science of physics […] [b]y the nineteenth century physics was a fully mature empirical science, operating independently of philosophy."</ref>

;Early Modern
{{Main article|17th-century philosophy|18th-century philosophy|Early modern philosophy}}
[[File:JohnLocke.png|thumb|[[John Locke]]]]

Some central topics of philosophy in this period include the nature of the mind and its relation to the body, the implications of the new natural sciences for traditional theological topics such as free will and God, and the emergence of a secular basis for moral and political philosophy.<ref name="philosophy9">Kenny, ''A New History of Western Philosophy'', vol. 3, pp. 212–331.</ref> These trends first distinctively coalesce in [[Francis Bacon]]'s call for a new, empirical program for expanding knowledge, and soon found massively influential form in the mechanical physics and rationalist metaphysics of [[René Descartes]].<ref name="philosophical10">Nadler, ''A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'', pp. 2–3: "Why should the early modern period in philosophy begin with Descartes and Bacon, for example, rather than with Erasmus and Montaigne? […] Suffice it to say that at the beginning of the seventeenth century, and especially with Bacon and Descartes, certain questions and concerns come to the fore—a variety of issues that motivated the inquiries and debates that would characterize much philosophical thinking for the next two centuries."</ref>

Other notable modern philosophers include [[Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[David Hume|Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]].<ref name="philosophical12">Rutherford, ''The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'', p. 1: "Most often this [period] has been associated with the achievements of a handful of great thinkers: the so-called 'rationalists' (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz) and 'empiricists' (Locke, Berkeley, Hume), whose inquiries culminate in Kant's 'Critical philosophy.' These canonical figures have been celebrated for the depth and rigor of their treatments of perennial philosophical questions..."</ref><ref name="traditional">Nadler, ''A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy'', p. 2: "The study of early modern philosophy demands that we pay attention to a wide variety of questions and an expansive pantheon of thinkers: the traditional canonical figures (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume), to be sure, but also a large 'supporting cast'..."</ref><ref name="philosophical13" /> Many other contributors were philosophers, scientists, medical doctors, and politicians. A short list includes [[Galileo Galilei]], [[Pierre Gassendi]], [[Blaise Pascal]], [[Nicolas Malebranche]], [[Isaac Newton]], [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Christian Wolff]], [[Montesquieu]], [[Pierre Bayle]], [[Thomas Reid]], [[Jean d'Alembert]], [[Adam Smith]], and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]].

The approximate end of the early modern period is most often identified with [[Immanuel Kant]]'s systematic attempt to limit metaphysics, justify scientific knowledge, and reconcile both of these with morality and freedom.<ref name="rutherford" /><ref name="philosophy14">Kenny, ''A New History of Western Philosophy'', vol. 3, p. xiii.</ref><ref name="philosophy15">Nadler, A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, p. 3.</ref>

[[File:Immanuel_Kant_(painted_portrait).jpg|left|thumb|216x216px|Immanuel Kant]]

[[File:Painting_of_David_Hume.jpg|thumb|[[David Hume]]]]

;19th-century

{{Main article|19th-century philosophy}}
[[File:Nietzsche187a.jpg|right|thumb|217x217px|[[Friedrich Nietzsche]] ]]
Later modern philosophy is usually considered to begin after the philosophy of [[Immanuel Kant]] at the beginning of the 19th century.<ref name="Shand" />

German philosophy exercised broad influence in this century, owing in part to the dominance of the German university system.<ref name="universities" /> [[German idealist]]s, such as [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]], and [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling]], transformed the work of Kant by maintaining that the world is constituted by a rational or mind-like process, and as such is entirely knowable.<ref name="frederick" /> [[Arthur Schopenhauer]]'s identification of this world-constituting process as an irrational [[will to live]] influenced later 19th- and early 20th-century thinking, such as the work of [[Friedrich Nietzsche]].

The [[19th-century philosophy|19th century]] took the radical notions of self-organization and intrinsic order from Goethe and Kantian metaphysics, and proceeded to produce a long elaboration on the tension between systematization and organic development. Foremost was the work of [[Hegel]], whose ''Logic'' and ''Phenomenology of Spirit'' produced a "dialectical" framework for ordering of knowledge.
[[File:G.W.F._Hegel_(by_Sichling,_after_Sebbers).jpg|left|thumb|160x160px|Hegel]]
As with the 18th century, developments in science arose from philosophy and also challenged philosophy: most importantly the work of Charles Darwin, which was based on the idea of organic self-regulation found in philosophers such as Smith, but fundamentally challenged established conceptions.

After Hegel's death in 1831, 19th-century philosophy largely turned against idealism in favor of varieties of philosophical [[Naturalism (philosophy)|naturalism]], such as the [[positivism]] of [[Auguste Comte]], the empiricism of [[John Stuart Mill]], and the materialism of [[Karl Marx]]. Logic began a period of its most significant advances since the inception of the discipline, as increasing mathematical precision opened entire fields of inference to formalization in the work of [[George Boole]] and [[Gottlob Frege]].<ref name="transformation" /> Other philosophers who initiated lines of thought that would continue to shape philosophy into the 20th century include:
* [[Gottlob Frege]] and [[Henry Sidgwick]], whose work in logic and ethics, respectively, provided the tools for early [[analytic philosophy]].
* [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] and [[William James]], who founded [[pragmatism]].
* [[Søren Kierkegaard]] and [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], who laid the groundwork for [[existentialism]] and [[post-structuralism]].

== Contemporary approaches ==

{{main article|Contemporary philosophy}}
The three major contemporary approaches to academic philosophy are [[Analytic philosophy]], [[continental philosophy]] and [[pragmatism]].<ref>Nicholas Joll, http://www.iep.utm.edu/con-meta/</ref> They are neither exhaustive nor mutually exclusive.

The [[20th-century philosophy|20th century]] deals with the upheavals produced by a series of conflicts within philosophical discourse over the basis of knowledge, with classical certainties overthrown, and new social, economic, scientific and logical problems. 20th century philosophy was set for a series of attempts to reform and preserve, and to alter or abolish, older knowledge systems. Seminal figures include [[Gottlob Frege]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[Martin Heidegger]], [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], and [[Edmund Husserl]].

Since the Second World War, contemporary philosophy has been divided mostly into [[Analytic philosophy|analytic]] and [[Continental philosophy|continental]] traditions; the former carried in the English speaking world and the latter on the continent of Europe. The perceived conflict between continental and analytic schools of philosophy remains prominent, despite increasing skepticism regarding the distinction's usefulness.

=== Analytic ===
{{Main article|Analytic philosophy}}
[[File:Gottlob_Frege_(Emil_Tesch).png|thumb|[[Gottlob Frege]] ]]
In the English-speaking world, [[analytic philosophy]] became the dominant school for much of the 20th century.

The term ''analytic philosophy'' roughly designates a group of philosophical methods that stress detailed argumentation, attention to semantics, use of classical logic and non-classical logics and clarity of meaning above all other criteria. Though the movement has broadened, it was a cohesive school in the first half of the century. Analytic philosophers were shaped strongly by [[logical positivism]], united by the notion that philosophical problems could and should be solved by attention to [[logic]] and [[language]].

[[Bertrand Russell]] and [[G.E. Moore]] are also often counted as founders of analytic philosophy, beginning with their rejection of British idealism, their defense of realism and the emphasis they laid on the legitimacy of analysis.
Russell's classic works ''The Principles of Mathematics'',<ref name="russell" /> ''[[On Denoting]]'' and ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' with [[Alfred North Whitehead]], aside from greatly promoting the use of mathematical logic in philosophy, set the ground for much of the research program in the early stages of the analytic tradition, emphasizing such problems as: the reference of proper names, whether 'existence' is a property, the nature of propositions, the analysis of definite descriptions, and discussions on the foundations of mathematics. These works also explored issues of ontological commitment and metaphysical problems regarding time, the nature of matter, mind, persistence and change, which Russell often tackled with the aid of mathematical logic.

[[Gottlob Frege]]'s ''The Foundations of Arithmetic'' was the first analytic work, according to [[Michael Dummett]] (''Origins of Analytical Philosophy).'' Frege took "the linguistic turn," analyzing philosophical problems through language. Some analytic philosophers held that philosophical problems arise through misuse of language or because of misunderstandings of the logic of human language.

In 1921, [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], who studied under Russell at Cambridge, published his ''[[Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus]]'', which gave a rigidly "logical" account of linguistic and philosophical issues. Years later, he reversed a number of the positions he set out in the ''Tractatus'', in for example his second major work, ''[[Philosophical Investigations]]'' (1953). ''Investigations'' was influential in the development of "ordinary language philosophy," which was promoted by [[Gilbert Ryle]], [[J.L. Austin]], and a few others.

In the United States, meanwhile, the philosophy of Quine was having a major influence, with the paper [[Two Dogmas of Empiricism]]. In that paper Quine criticizes the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements, arguing that a clear conception of analyticity is unattainable.
[[File:Patricia_Churchland_at_STEP_2005_a.jpg|right|thumb|194x194px|[[Patricia Churchland]] ]]
Notable students of Quine include [[Donald Davidson (philosopher)|Donald Davidson]] and [[Daniel Dennett]]. The later work of Russell and the philosophy of [[Willard Van Orman Quine]] are influential exemplars of the naturalist approach dominant in the second half of the 20th century. But the diversity of analytic philosophy from the 1970s onward defies easy generalization: the naturalism of Quine and his epigoni was in some precincts superseded by a "new metaphysics" of [[possible worlds]], as in the influential work of [[David Kellogg Lewis|David Lewis]]. Recently, the [[experimental philosophy]] movement has sought to reappraise philosophical problems through social science research techniques.

Some influential figures in contemporary analytic philosophy are: Timothy Williamson, [[David Kellogg Lewis|David Lewis]], [[John Searle]], [[Thomas Nagel]], [[Hilary Putnam]], [[Michael Dummett]], [[Peter van Inwagen]], [[Saul Kripke]] and [[Patricia Churchland]].

Analytic philosophy has sometimes been accused of not contributing to the political debate or to traditional questions in aesthetics. However, with the appearance of ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' by [[John Rawls]] and ''[[Anarchy, State, and Utopia]]'' by [[Robert Nozick]], analytic political philosophy acquired respectability. Analytic philosophers have also shown depth in their investigations of aesthetics, with [[Roger Scruton]], [[Nelson Goodman]], [[Arthur Danto]] and others developing the subject to its current shape.

=== Continental ===
{{Main article|Continental philosophy}}

Continental philosophy is a set of 19th- and 20th-century philosophical traditions from mainland Europe. 20th-century movements such as [[German idealism]], [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]], [[existentialism]], modern [[hermeneutics]], [[critical theory]], [[structuralism]], [[poststructuralism]] and others are included within this loose category. While identifying any non-trivial common factor in all these schools of thought is bound to be controversial, Michael E. Rosen has hypothesized a few common Continental themes: that the natural sciences cannot replace the human sciences; that the thinker is affected by the conditions of experience (one's place and time in history); that philosophy is both theoretical and practical; that metaphilosophy or reflection upon the methods and nature of philosophy itself is an important part of philosophy proper.

The founder of phenomenology, [[Edmund Husserl]], sought to study consciousness as experienced from a first-person perspective, while [[Martin Heidegger]] drew on the ideas of Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Husserl to propose an unconventional [[existential]] approach to [[ontology]]. In the [[Arabic language|Arabic-speaking]] world, [[Arab nationalism|Arab nationalist]] philosophy became the dominant school of thought, involving philosophers such as [[Michel Aflaq]], [[Zaki al-Arsuzi]], [[Salah al-Din al-Bitar]] of [[Ba'athism]] and [[Sati' al-Husri]].

Phenomenologically oriented metaphysics undergirded [[existentialism]] (Heidegger, Sartre, [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], [[Albert Camus]]) and finally [[poststructuralism]] ([[Gilles Deleuze]], [[Jean-François Lyotard]], [[Michel Foucault]], [[Jacques Derrida]]). The [[Psychoanalysis|psychoanalytic]] work of [[Sigmund Freud]], [[Jacques Lacan]], [[Julia Kristeva]], and others has also been influential in contemporary continental thought. Conversely, some philosophers have attempted to define and rehabilitate older traditions of philosophy. Most notably, [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] and [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] have both, albeit in different ways, revived the tradition of [[Aristotelianism]].

===German idealism===
{{Main article|German idealism}}
[[File:Immanuel_Kant_(painted_portrait).jpg|thumb|[[Immanuel Kant]]]]

Transcendental idealism, advocated by [[Immanuel Kant]], is the view that there are limits on what can be understood, since there is much that cannot be brought under the conditions of objective judgment. Kant wrote his ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' (1781–1787) in an attempt to reconcile the conflicting approaches of rationalism and empiricism, and to establish a new groundwork for studying metaphysics. Although Kant held that objective knowledge of the world required the mind to impose a [[Conceptual framework|conceptual]] or [[categorical framework]] on the stream of pure sensory data—a framework including space and time themselves—he maintained that ''things-in-themselves'' existed independently of human perceptions and judgments; he was therefore not an idealist in any simple sense. Kant's account of ''things-in-themselves'' is both controversial and highly complex. Continuing his work, [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte]] and [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling|Friedrich Schelling]] dispensed with belief in the independent existence of the world, and created a thoroughgoing idealist philosophy.

The most notable work of this [[German idealism]] was [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|G. W. F. Hegel]]'s ''[[Phenomenology of Spirit]]'', of 1807. Hegel admitted his ideas were not new, but that all the previous philosophies had been incomplete. His goal was to correctly finish their job. Hegel asserts that the twin aims of philosophy are to account for the contradictions apparent in human experience (which arise, for instance, out of the supposed contradictions between "being" and "not being"), and also simultaneously to resolve and preserve these contradictions by showing their compatibility at a higher level of examination ("being" and "not being" are resolved with "becoming"). This program of acceptance and reconciliation of contradictions is known as the "Hegelian [[dialectic]]".

Philosophers influenced by Hegel include [[Ludwig Andreas Feuerbach]], who coined the term projection as pertaining to humans' inability to recognize anything in the external world without projecting qualities of ourselves upon those things; [[Karl Marx]]; [[Friedrich Engels]]; and the [[British idealism|British idealists]], notably [[T. H. Green]], [[J. M. E. McTaggart]] and [[F. H. Bradley]]. Few 20th-century philosophers have embraced idealism. However, quite a few have embraced Hegelian dialectic. Immanuel Kant's "Copernican Turn" also remains an important philosophical concept today.

=== Phenomenology ===
{{Main article|Phenomenology (philosophy)}}
[[File:Edmund_Husserl_1910s.jpg|right|thumb|230x230px|[[Edmund Husserl]] ]]
[[Edmund Husserl]]'s [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] was an ambitious attempt to lay the foundations for an account of the structure of conscious experience in general.<ref name="Ref-1" /> An important part of Husserl's phenomenological project was to show that all conscious acts are directed at or about objective content, a feature that Husserl called ''[[intentionality]]''.<ref name="Dreyfus" /> Husserl published only a few works in his lifetime, which treat phenomenology mainly in abstract methodological terms; but he left an enormous quantity of unpublished concrete analyses. Husserl's work was immediately influential in Germany, with the foundation of phenomenological schools in Munich and Göttingen. Phenomenology later achieved international fame through the work of such philosophers as [[Martin Heidegger]] (formerly Husserl's research assistant), [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], and [[Jean-Paul Sartre]]. Through the work of Heidegger and Sartre, Husserl's focus on subjective experience influenced aspects of existentialism.

=== Existentialism===
{{Main article|Existentialism}}
Existentialism is a term applied to the work of a number of late 19th- and 20th-century philosophers who, despite profound doctrinal differences,<ref name="existentialism" /><ref name="philosophy25">''Oxford Companion to Philosophy'', ed. Ted Honderich, New York (1995), page 259.</ref> shared the belief that philosophical thinking begins with the human subject—not merely the thinking subject, but the acting, feeling, living human individual.<ref name="existentialism26" /> In existentialism, the individual's starting point is characterized by what has been called "the existential attitude", or a sense of disorientation and confusion in the face of an apparently meaningless or absurd world.<ref name="existentialism27" /> Many existentialists have also regarded traditional systematic or academic philosophy, in both style and content, as too abstract and remote from concrete human experience.<ref name="existentialism28" /><ref name="existentialism29" />
[[File:Kierkegaard.jpg|left|thumb|[[Søren Kierkegaard]]]]

Although they did not use the term, the 19th-century philosophers [[Søren Kierkegaard]] and [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] are widely regarded as the fathers of existentialism. Their influence, however, has extended beyond existentialist thought.<ref name="kierkegaard" /><ref name="Bob" /><ref name="existentialists" />

==== Structuralism and post-structuralism ====
{{Main article|Structuralism|Post-structuralism}}
[[File:Ferdinand_de_Saussure.jpg|thumb|[[Ferdinand de Saussure]]]]

Inaugurated by the linguist [[Ferdinand de Saussure]], structuralism sought to clarify systems of signs through analyzing the [[discourse]]s they both limit and make possible. Saussure conceived of the sign as being delimited by all the other signs in the system, and ideas as being incapable of existence prior to linguistic structure, which articulates thought. This led continental thought away from humanism, and toward what was termed the decentering of man: language is no longer spoken by man to express a true inner self, but language speaks man.

Structuralism sought the province of a hard science, but its positivism soon came under fire by poststructuralism, a wide field of thinkers, some of whom were once themselves structuralists, but later came to criticize it. Structuralists believed they could analyze systems from an external, objective standing, for example, but the poststructuralists argued that this is incorrect, that one cannot transcend structures and thus analysis is itself determined by what it examines. While the distinction between the signifier and signified was treated as crystalline by structuralists, poststructuralists asserted that every attempt to grasp the signified results in more signifiers, so meaning is always in a state of being deferred, making an ultimate interpretation impossible.

Structuralism came to dominate continental philosophy throughout the 1960s and early 1970s, encompassing thinkers as diverse as [[Claude Lévi-Strauss]], [[Roland Barthes]] and [[Jacques Lacan]]. Post-structuralism came to predominate from the 1970s onwards, including thinkers such as [[Michel Foucault]], [[Jacques Derrida]], [[Gilles Deleuze]] and even [[Roland Barthes]]; it incorporated a critique of structuralism's limitations.

=== Pragmatism ===

{{Main article|Pragmatism|Instrumentalism}}
[[File:Wm james.jpg|thumb|[[William James]]]]
Pragmatism asserts that the truth of beliefs consists in their usefulness and efficacy rather than their correspondence with reality.<ref name="Rorty" /> [[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce]] and [[William James|James]] were its co-founders and it was later modified by [[John Dewey|Dewey]] as [[instrumentalism]]. Since the usefulness of any belief at any time might be contingent on circumstance, Peirce and James conceptualised final truth as something established only by the future, final settlement of all opinion.<ref name="Putnam" />

Pragmatism attempted to find a scientific concept of truth that does not depend on personal insight (revelation) or reference to some metaphysical realm. It interpreted the meaning of a statement by the effect its acceptance would have on practice. Inquiry taken far enough is thus the only path to truth.<ref>Peirce, C. S. (1878), "[[s:How to Make Our Ideas Clear|How to Make Our Ideas Clear]]", ''Popular Science Monthly'', v. 12, 286–302. Reprinted often, including ''Collected Papers'' v. 5, paragraphs 388–410 and ''Essential Peirce'' v. 1, 124–41. See end of §II for the pragmatic maxim. See third and fourth paragraphs in §IV for the discoverability of truth and the real by sufficient investigation. Also see quotes from Peirce from across the years in the entries for [http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/truth.html "Truth"] and [http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/pragmatismmaxim.html "Pragmatism, Maxim of..."] in the ''Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms'', Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, editors, University of Helsinki.</ref>

For [[Charles Sanders Peirce|Peirce]] commitment to inquiry was essential to truth-finding, implied by the idea and hope that inquiry is not fruitless. The interpretation of these principles has been subject to discussion ever since. Peirce's [[Pragmatic maxim|maxim of pragmatism]] is, "Consider what effects, which might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object."<ref name="paragraphs" />

Critics accused pragmatism falling victim to a simple fallacy: that because something that is true proves useful, that usefulness is an appropriate basis for its truthfulness.<ref name="Pratt" /> Pragmatist thinkers include Dewey, [[George Santayana|Santayana]], Quine and [[C. I. Lewis|Lewis]]. Pragmatism was later worked on by Rorty, Lachs, [[Donald Davidson (philosopher)|Davidson]], [[Susan Haack|Haack]] and [[Hilary Putnam|Putnam]].



== Other approaches ==
=== Other approaches ===
A variety of other academic and non-academic approaches have been explored.
A variety of other academic and non-academic approaches have been explored.


=== Applied philosophy {{anchor|Applied philosophy}} ===
==== Applied philosophy {{anchor|Applied philosophy}} ====
<!--This section is linked from [[List of academic disciplines]] and target of redirect [[Applied philosophy]] -->
<!--This section is linked from [[List of academic disciplines]] and target of redirect [[Applied philosophy]] -->
[[File:Martin Luther King Jr NYWTS.jpg|right|thumb|206x206px|[[Martin Luther King Jr]] ]]
[[File:Martin Luther King Jr NYWTS.jpg|right|thumb|206x206px|[[Martin Luther King Jr]] ]]
Line 196: Line 324:
Other important applications can be found in [[epistemology]], which aid in understanding the requisites for knowledge, sound evidence and justified belief (important in [[law]], [[economics]], [[decision theory]] and a number of other disciplines). The [[philosophy of science]] discusses the underpinnings of the [[scientific method]] and has affected the nature of scientific investigation and argumentation. Philosophy thus has fundamental implications for science as a whole. For example, the strictly empirical approach of [[B. F. Skinner]]'s behaviorism affected for decades the approach of the American psychological establishment. [[Deep ecology]] and [[animal rights]] examine the moral situation of humans as occupants of a world that has non-human occupants to consider also. [[Aesthetics]] can help to interpret discussions of [[music]], [[literature]], the [[plastic arts]] and the whole artistic dimension of life. In general, the various philosophies strive to provide practical activities with a deeper understanding of the theoretical or conceptual underpinnings of their fields.
Other important applications can be found in [[epistemology]], which aid in understanding the requisites for knowledge, sound evidence and justified belief (important in [[law]], [[economics]], [[decision theory]] and a number of other disciplines). The [[philosophy of science]] discusses the underpinnings of the [[scientific method]] and has affected the nature of scientific investigation and argumentation. Philosophy thus has fundamental implications for science as a whole. For example, the strictly empirical approach of [[B. F. Skinner]]'s behaviorism affected for decades the approach of the American psychological establishment. [[Deep ecology]] and [[animal rights]] examine the moral situation of humans as occupants of a world that has non-human occupants to consider also. [[Aesthetics]] can help to interpret discussions of [[music]], [[literature]], the [[plastic arts]] and the whole artistic dimension of life. In general, the various philosophies strive to provide practical activities with a deeper understanding of the theoretical or conceptual underpinnings of their fields.


== Society ==
== Philosophy and Society ==
Some of those who study philosophy become professional philosophers, typically by working as [[professor]]s who teach, research and write in academic institutions.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://philosophy.as.uky.edu/where-can-philosophy-take-me|title=Where Can Philosophy Take Me? {{!}} Philosophy|website=philosophy.as.uky.edu|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref> However, most students of academic philosophy later contribute to law, journalism, religion, sciences, politics, business, or various arts.<ref name="whystudyphilosophy.com"/><ref>{{Cite news|url=http://www.nytimes.com/1997/12/26/business/philosophers-find-the-degree-pays-off-in-life-and-in-work.html|title=Philosophers Find the Degree Pays Off in Life And in Work|last=Cropper|first=Carol Marie|date=1997-12-26|newspaper=The New York Times|issn=0362-4331|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref> For example, public figures who have degrees in philosophy include comedians [[Steve Martin]] and [[Ricky Gervais]], filmmaker [[Terrence Malick]], [[Pope John Paul II]], Wikipedia co-founder [[Larry Sanger]], Supreme Court Justice [[Stephen Breyer|Stephen Bryer]] and vice presidential candidate [[Carly Fiorina]].<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.mansfield.edu/philosophy/famous-philosophy-majors.cfm|title=Famous Philosophy Majors {{!}} Mansfield University|last=Marketing|first=Mansfield University Department of|website=www.mansfield.edu|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web|url=http://dailynous.com/2014/12/08/famous-philosophy-majors-poster/|title=Famous Philosophy Majors Poster (updated with new link)|last=W|first=Justin|date=2014-12-08|website=Daily Nous|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref>
Some of those who study philosophy become professional philosophers, typically by working as [[professor]]s who teach, research and write in academic institutions.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://philosophy.as.uky.edu/where-can-philosophy-take-me|title=Where Can Philosophy Take Me? {{!}} Philosophy|website=philosophy.as.uky.edu|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref> However, most students of academic philosophy later contribute to law, journalism, religion, sciences, politics, business, or various arts.<ref name="whystudyphilosophy.com"/><ref>{{Cite news|url=http://www.nytimes.com/1997/12/26/business/philosophers-find-the-degree-pays-off-in-life-and-in-work.html|title=Philosophers Find the Degree Pays Off in Life And in Work|last=Cropper|first=Carol Marie|date=1997-12-26|newspaper=The New York Times|issn=0362-4331|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref> For example, public figures who have degrees in philosophy include comedians [[Steve Martin]] and [[Ricky Gervais]], filmmaker [[Terrence Malick]], [[Pope John Paul II]], Wikipedia co-founder [[Larry Sanger]], Supreme Court Justice [[Stephen Breyer|Stephen Bryer]] and vice presidential candidate [[Carly Fiorina]].<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.mansfield.edu/philosophy/famous-philosophy-majors.cfm|title=Famous Philosophy Majors {{!}} Mansfield University|last=Marketing|first=Mansfield University Department of|website=www.mansfield.edu|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web|url=http://dailynous.com/2014/12/08/famous-philosophy-majors-poster/|title=Famous Philosophy Majors Poster (updated with new link)|last=W|first=Justin|date=2014-12-08|website=Daily Nous|access-date=2016-05-02}}</ref>



Revision as of 07:07, 1 December 2016

Philosophy (from Greek φιλοσοφία, philosophia, literally "love of wisdom"[1][2][3][4]) is the study of general and fundamental problems concerning matters such as existence, knowledge, values, reason, mind, and language.[5][6] The term was probably coined by Pythagoras (c. 570 – c. 495 BC). Philosophical methods include questioning, critical discussion, rational argument and systematic presentation.[7][8] Classic philosophical questions include: Is it possible to know anything and to prove it?[9][10][11] What is most real? However, philosophers might also pose more practical and concrete questions such as: Is there a best way to live? Is it better to be just or unjust (if one can get away with it)?[12] Do humans have free will?[13]

Historically, "philosophy" encompassed any body of knowledge.[14] From the time of Ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle to the 19th century, "natural philosophy" encompassed astronomy, medicine and physics.[15] For example, Newton's 1687 Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy later became classified as a book of physics. In the 19th century, the growth of modern research universities led academic philosophy and other disciplines to professionalize and specialize.[16][17] In the modern era, some investigations that were traditionally part of philosophy became separate academic disciplines, including psychology, sociology, linguistics and economics.

Other investigations closely related to art, science, politics, or other pursuits remained part of philosophy. For example, is beauty objective or subjective?[18][19] Are there many scientific methods or just one?[20] Is political utopia a hopeful dream or hopeless fantasy?[21][22][23] Major sub-fields of academic philosophy include metaphysics ("concerned with the fundamental nature of reality and being"),[24] epistemology (about the "nature and grounds of knowledge [and]...its limits and validity" [25]), ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, logic, philosophy of science and the history of Western philosophy.

Since the 20th century professional philosophers contribute to society primarily as professors, researchers and writers. However, many of those who study philosophy in undergraduate or graduate programs contribute in the fields of law, journalism, politics, religion, science, business and various art and entertainment activities.[26]

Introduction

Knowledge

Traditionally, the term "philosophy" referred to any body of knowledge.[14][27] In this sense, philosophy is closely related to religion, mathematics, natural science, education and politics. Newton's 1687 "Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy" is classified in the 2000s as a book of physics; he used the term "natural philosophy" because it used to encompass disciplines that later became associated with sciences such as astronomy, medicine and physics.[15]

Philosophy was traditionally divided into three major branches:

This division is not obsolete but has changed. Natural philosophy has split into the various natural sciences, especially astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology and cosmology. Moral philosophy has birthed the social sciences, but still includes value theory (including aesthetics, ethics, political philosophy, etc.). Metaphysical philosophy has birthed formal sciences such as logic, mathematics and philosophy of science, but still includes epistemology, cosmology and others.

Philosophical progress

Many philosophical debates that began in ancient times are still debated today. Colin McGinn and others claim that no philosophical progress has occurred during that interval.[29] Chalmers and others, by contrast, see progress in philosophy similar to that in science,[30] while Talbot Brewer argued that "progress" is the wrong standard by which to judge philosophical activity.[31]

Philosophy and Culture

In one sense, philosophy is synonymous with wisdom or learning. In that sense, all cultures have a philosophical tradition.

Western philosophy

Western philosophy dates to the Greek philosophers, who were active in Ancient Greece beginning in the 6th century BC. Pythagoras distinguished himself from other "wise ones" by calling himself a mere lover of wisdom, suggesting that he was not wise.[32] Socrates used this title and insisted that he possessed no wisdom but was a pursuer of wisdom.[33] Socrates' student Plato is often credited as the founder of Western philosophy. The philosopher Alfred North Whitehead said of Plato: "The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato. I do not mean the systematic scheme of thought which scholars have doubtfully extracted from his writings. I allude to the wealth of general ideas scattered through them."[34]

Eastern philosophy
File:Zarathushtra.jpg
The Iranian prophet Zarathustra is credited as the founder of Zoroastrianism.

Eastern philosophy is a term that encompasses the many philosophical currents originating outside Europe, including China, India, Japan, Persia and other regions. They have their own timelines, regions and philosophers. Major traditions include:

Categories

Philosopher questions can be grouped into categories. These groupings allow philosophers to focus on a set of similar topics and interact with other thinkers who are interested in the same questions. The groupings also make philosophy easier for students to approach. Students can learn the basic principles involved in one aspect of the field without being overwhelmed with the entire set of philosophical theories.

Various sources present different categorical schemes. The categories adopted in this article aim for breadth and simplicity.

These five major branches can be separated into sub-branches and each sub-branch contains many specific fields of study.[35]

These divisions are neither exhaustive, nor mutually exclusive. (A philosopher might specialize in Kantian epistemology, or Platonic aesthetics, or modern political philosophy.) Furthermore, these philosophical inquiries sometimes overlap with each other and with other inquiries such as science, religion or mathematics.[37]

Metaphysics

Metaphysics is the study of the most general features of reality, such as existence, time, objects and their properties, wholes and their parts, events, processes and causation and the relationship between mind and body. Metaphysics includes cosmology, the study of the world in its entirety and ontology, the study of being.

A major point of debate revolves between realism, which holds that there are entities that exist independently of their mental perception and idealism, which holds that reality is mentally constructed or otherwise immaterial. Metaphysics deals with the topic of identity. Essence is the set of attributes that make an object what it fundamentally is and without which it loses its identity while accident is a property that the object has, without which the object can still retain its identity. Particulars are objects that are said to exist in space and time, as opposed to abstract objects, such as numbers, and universals, which are properties held by multiple particulars, such as redness or a gender. The type of existence, if any, of universals and abstract objects is an issue of debate.

Epistemology

Dignaga founded Buddhist epistemology (pramana)

Epistemology is the study of knowledge (Greek episteme).[38] Epistemologists study the putative sources of knowledge, including intuition, a priori reason, memory, perceptual knowledge, self-knowledge and testimony. They also ask: What is truth? Is knowledge justified true belief? Are any beliefs justified? Putative knowledge includes propositional knowledge (knowledge that something is the case), know-how (knowledge of how to do something) and acquaintance (familiarity with someone or something). Epistemologists examine these and ask whether knowledge is really possible.

Skepticism is the position which doubts claims to knowledge. The regress argument, a fundamental problem in epistemology, occurs when, in order to completely prove any statement, its justification itself needs to be supported by another justification. This chain can go on forever, called infinitism, it can eventually rely on basic beliefs that are left unproven, called foundationalism, or it can go in a circle so that a statement is included in its own chain of justification, called coherentism.

Rationalism is the emphasis on reasoning as a source of knowledge. It is associated with a priori knowledge, which is independent of experience, such as math and logical deduction. Empiricism is the emphasis on observational evidence via sensory experience as the source of knowledge.

Among the numerous topics within metaphysics and epistemology, broadly construed are:

Value theory

Value theory (or axiology) is the major branch of philosophy that addresses topics such as goodness, beauty and justice. Value theory includes ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, feminist philosophy, philosophy of law and more.

Ethics

The Beijing imperial college was an intellectual center for Confucian ethics and classics during the Yuan, Ming and Qing dynasties.

Ethics, or "moral philosophy", studies and considers what is good and bad conduct, right and wrong values, and good and evil. Its primary investigations include how to live a good life and identifying standards of morality. It also includes meta-investigations about whether a best way to live or related standards exists. The main branches of ethics are normative ethics, meta-ethics and applied ethics.

A major point of debate revolves around consequentialism, where actions are judged by the potential results of the act, such as to maximize happiness, called utilitarianism, and deontology, where actions are judged by how they adhere to principles, irrespective of negative ends.

Aesthetics

Aesthetics is the "critical reflection on art, culture and nature."[39][40] It addresses the nature of art, beauty and taste, enjoyment, emotional values, perception and with the creation and appreciation of beauty.[41][42] It is more precisely defined as the study of sensory or sensori-emotional values, sometimes called judgments of sentiment and taste.[43] It divides into art theory, literary theory, film theory and music theory. An example from art theory is to discern the set of principles underlying the work of a particular artist or artistic movement such as the Cubist aesthetic.[44] The philosophy of film analyzes films and filmmakers for their philosophical content and explores film (images, cinema, etc.) as a medium for philosophical reflection and expression.[citation needed]

Political philosophy

Thomas Hobbes

Political philosophy is the study of government and the relationship of individuals (or families and clans) to communities including the state. It includes questions about justice, law, property and the rights and obligations of the citizen. Politics and ethics are traditionally linked subjects, as both discuss the question of what how people should live together.

Other branches of value theory:

There are a variety of branches of value theory.

  • Philosophy of law (often called jurisprudence) explores the varying theories explaining the nature and interpretation of laws.
  • Philosophy of education analyzes the definition and content of education, as well as the goals and challenges of educators.
  • Feminist philosophy explores questions surrounding gender, sexuality and the body including the nature of feminism itself as a social and philosophical movement.
  • Philosophy of sport analyzes sports, games and other forms of play as sociological and uniquely human activities.

Logic, science and mathematics

Many academic disciplines generated philosophical inquiry. The relationship between "X" and the "philosophy of X" is debated. Richard Feynman argued that the philosophy of a topic is irrelevant to its primary study, saying that "philosophy of science is as useful to scientists as ornithology is to birds." Curtis White, by contrast, argued that philosophical tools are essential to humanities, sciences and social sciences.[45]

The topics of philosophy of science are numbers, symbols and the formal methods of reasoning as employed in the social sciences and natural sciences.

Logic

Logic is the study of reasoning and argument. An argument is "a connected series of statements intended to establish a proposition." The connected series of statements are "premises" and the proposition is the conclusion. For example:

  1. All humans are mortal. (premise)
  2. Socrates is a human. (premise)
  3. Therefore, Socrates is mortal. (conclusion)

Deductive reasoning is when, given certain premises, conclusions are unavoidably implied. Rules of inference are used to infer conclusions such as, modus ponens, where given “A” and “If A then B”, then “B” must be concluded.

Because sound reasoning is an essential element of all sciences,[46] social sciences and humanities disciplines, logic became a formal science. Sub-fields include mathematical logic, philosophical logic, Modal logic, computational logic and non-classical logics. A major issue in the philosophy of mathematics revolves around whether mathematical entities are objective and discovered, called mathematical realism, or invented, called mathematical antirealism.

Philosophy of science

The ideas of Ibn al-Haytham were instrumental in the development of the modern Scientific method.

This branch explores the foundations, methods, history, implications and purpose of science. Many of its sub-divisions correspond to a specific branch of science. For example, philosophy of biology deals specifically with the metaphysical, epistemological and ethical issues in the biomedical and life sciences. The philosophy of mathematics studies the philosophical assumptions, foundations and implications of mathematics.

History of philosophy

Some philosophers specialize in one or more historical periods. The history of philosophy (study of a specific period, individual or school) is related to but not the same as the philosophy of history (the theoretical aspect of history, which deals with questions such as the nature of historical evidence and the possibility of objectivity).

Hegel's Lectures on the Philosophy of History influenced many philosophers to interpret truth in light of history, a view called historicism.

History

Western philosophy has a long history dating back to the time of Socrates. It is conventionally divided into three large eras: ancient, medieval, and modern. Philosophy in the 20th century to present is considered "Contemporary philosophy". The history of philosophy is a rich field of study. This article does not aim for comprehensive detail but for a brief introduction to each period, with relevant links to other articles. The three historical periods are divided roughly as follows:

  • Ancient (from 585 BC-400 AD)
  • Medieval (400 - 1500)
  • Modern (1500 - 1900)

Ancient

Plato (left) and Aristotle (right): detail from The School of Athens by Raffaello Sanzio, 1509
Pre-Socratic period
Ionia, source of early Greek philosophy, in western Asia Minor

Ancient philosophers first articulated questions about the "arche" (the cause or first principle) of the universe. Western Philosophy is generally said to begin in the Greek cities of western Asia Minor (Ionia) with Thales of Miletus, who was active around 585 B.C. and was responsible for the opaque dictum, "all is water." His most noted students were respectively Anaximander (all is apeiron (roughly, the unlimited)) and Anaximenes of Miletus ("all is air"). Pythagoras, from the island of Samos off the coast of Ionia, later lived at Croton in southern Italy (Magna Graecia). Pythagoreans hold that "all is number," giving formal accounts in contrast to the previous material of the Ionians. They also believe in metempsychosis, the transmigration of souls, or reincarnation.

Socrates
Bust of Socrates

The key figure in Greek philosophy is Socrates. Socrates studied under several Sophists but transformed Greek philosophy into a unified and continuous project that is still pursued today. It is said that following a visit to the Oracle of Delphi he spent much of his life questioning anyone in Athens who would engage him, in order to disprove the oracular prophecy that there would be no man wiser than Socrates. Socrates used a critical approach called the "elenchus" or Socratic method to examine people's views. He aimed to study human things: the good life, justice, beauty, and virtue. Although Socrates wrote nothing himself, some of his many disciples wrote down his conversations. He was tried for corrupting the youth and impiety by the Greek democracy. He was found guilty and sentenced to death. Although his friends offered to help him escape from prison, he chose to remain in Athens and abide by his principles. His execution consisting in drinking the poison hemlock and he died in 399 B.C.

Plato

Socrates' most important student was Plato. Plato founded the Academy of Athens and wrote a number of dialogues, which applied the Socratic method of inquiry to examine philosophical problems. Some central ideas of Plato's dialogues are the immortality of the soul, the benefits of being just, that evil is ignorance, and the Theory of Forms. Forms are universal properties that constitute true reality and contrast with the changeable material things he called "becoming".

Aristotle

Plato's most outstanding student was Aristotle. Aristotle was perhaps the first truly systematic philosopher and scientist. He wrote books on physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, aesthetics, poetry, theater, music, rhetoric, politics and logic. Aristotelian logic was the first type of logic to attempt to categorize every valid syllogism. Aristotle tutored Alexander the Great. Aristotelian philosophy exercised considerable influence on almost all western philosophers, including Greek, Roman, Christian, Jewish, and Islamic thinkers.

The Neoplatonic and Christian philosophers of Late Antiquity.

Medieval

Early and late medieval philosophy

Medieval philosophy is the philosophy of Western Europe and the Middle East during the Middle Ages, roughly extending from the Christianization of the Roman Empire until the Renaissance.[47] Medieval philosophy is defined partly by the rediscovery and further development of classical Greek and Hellenistic philosophy, and partly by the need to address theological problems and to integrate the then widespread sacred doctrines of Abrahamic religion (Islam, Judaism, and Christianity) with secular learning. Early medieval philosophy was influenced by the likes of Stoicism, neo-Platonism, but, above all, the philosophy of Plato himself.

Some problems discussed throughout this period are the relation of faith to reason, the existence and unity of God, the object of theology and metaphysics, the problems of knowledge, of universals, and of individuation. The prominent figure of this period was St. Augustine who adopted Plato's thought and Christianized it in the 4th century and whose influence dominated medieval philosophy perhaps up to end of the era but was checked with the arrival of Aristotle's texts. Augustinianism was the preferred starting point for most philosophers (including the great St. Anselm of Canterbury) up until the 13th century.

St. Thomas Aquinas

Thomas Aquinas, the father of Thomism, was immensely influential in Catholic Europe; he placed a great emphasis on reason and argumentation, and was one of the first to use the new translation of Aristotle's metaphysical and epistemological writing.

Philosophers from the Middle Ages include the Christian philosophers Augustine of Hippo, Boethius, Anselm, Gilbert of Poitiers, Peter Abelard, Roger Bacon, Bonaventure, Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, William of Ockham and Jean Buridan; the Jewish philosophers Maimonides and Gersonides; and the Muslim philosophers Alkindus, Alfarabi, Alhazen, Avicenna, Algazel, Avempace, Abubacer, Ibn Khaldūn, and Averroes. The medieval tradition of Scholasticism continued to flourish as late as the 17th century, in figures such as Francisco Suarez and John of St. Thomas.

Late Medieval and Renaissance
Giordano Bruno

The Renaissance ("rebirth") was a period of transition between the Middle Ages and modern thought,[48] in which the recovery of classical texts helped shift philosophical interests away from technical studies in logic, metaphysics, and theology towards eclectic inquiries into morality, philology, and mysticism.[49][50] The study of the classics and the humane arts generally, such as history and literature, enjoyed a scholarly interest hitherto unknown in Christendom, a tendency referred to as humanism.[51][52] Displacing the medieval interest in metaphysics and logic, the humanists followed Petrarch in making man and his virtues the focus of philosophy.[53][54]

Modern

The term "modern philosophy" has multiple usages. For example, Thomas Hobbes is sometimes considered the first modern philosopher because he applied a systematic method to political philosophy.[55][56] By contrast, René Descartes is often considered the first modern philosopher because he grounded his philosophy in problems of knowledge, rather than problems of metaphysics.[57]

René Descartes

Modern philosophy and especially Enlightenment philosophy[58] is distinguished by its increasing independence from traditional authorities such as the Church, academia, and Aristotelianism;[59][60] a new focus on the foundations of knowledge and metaphysical system-building;[61][62] and the emergence of modern physics out of natural philosophy.[63]

Early Modern
John Locke

Some central topics of philosophy in this period include the nature of the mind and its relation to the body, the implications of the new natural sciences for traditional theological topics such as free will and God, and the emergence of a secular basis for moral and political philosophy.[64] These trends first distinctively coalesce in Francis Bacon's call for a new, empirical program for expanding knowledge, and soon found massively influential form in the mechanical physics and rationalist metaphysics of René Descartes.[65]

Other notable modern philosophers include Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant.[66][67][68] Many other contributors were philosophers, scientists, medical doctors, and politicians. A short list includes Galileo Galilei, Pierre Gassendi, Blaise Pascal, Nicolas Malebranche, Isaac Newton, Christian Wolff, Montesquieu, Pierre Bayle, Thomas Reid, Jean d'Alembert, Adam Smith, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau.

The approximate end of the early modern period is most often identified with Immanuel Kant's systematic attempt to limit metaphysics, justify scientific knowledge, and reconcile both of these with morality and freedom.[69][70][71]

Immanuel Kant
David Hume
19th-century
Friedrich Nietzsche

Later modern philosophy is usually considered to begin after the philosophy of Immanuel Kant at the beginning of the 19th century.[72]

German philosophy exercised broad influence in this century, owing in part to the dominance of the German university system.[73] German idealists, such as Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, and Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, transformed the work of Kant by maintaining that the world is constituted by a rational or mind-like process, and as such is entirely knowable.[74] Arthur Schopenhauer's identification of this world-constituting process as an irrational will to live influenced later 19th- and early 20th-century thinking, such as the work of Friedrich Nietzsche.

The 19th century took the radical notions of self-organization and intrinsic order from Goethe and Kantian metaphysics, and proceeded to produce a long elaboration on the tension between systematization and organic development. Foremost was the work of Hegel, whose Logic and Phenomenology of Spirit produced a "dialectical" framework for ordering of knowledge.

Hegel

As with the 18th century, developments in science arose from philosophy and also challenged philosophy: most importantly the work of Charles Darwin, which was based on the idea of organic self-regulation found in philosophers such as Smith, but fundamentally challenged established conceptions.

After Hegel's death in 1831, 19th-century philosophy largely turned against idealism in favor of varieties of philosophical naturalism, such as the positivism of Auguste Comte, the empiricism of John Stuart Mill, and the materialism of Karl Marx. Logic began a period of its most significant advances since the inception of the discipline, as increasing mathematical precision opened entire fields of inference to formalization in the work of George Boole and Gottlob Frege.[75] Other philosophers who initiated lines of thought that would continue to shape philosophy into the 20th century include:

Contemporary approaches

The three major contemporary approaches to academic philosophy are Analytic philosophy, continental philosophy and pragmatism.[76] They are neither exhaustive nor mutually exclusive.

The 20th century deals with the upheavals produced by a series of conflicts within philosophical discourse over the basis of knowledge, with classical certainties overthrown, and new social, economic, scientific and logical problems. 20th century philosophy was set for a series of attempts to reform and preserve, and to alter or abolish, older knowledge systems. Seminal figures include Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Edmund Husserl.

Since the Second World War, contemporary philosophy has been divided mostly into analytic and continental traditions; the former carried in the English speaking world and the latter on the continent of Europe. The perceived conflict between continental and analytic schools of philosophy remains prominent, despite increasing skepticism regarding the distinction's usefulness.

Analytic

Gottlob Frege

In the English-speaking world, analytic philosophy became the dominant school for much of the 20th century.

The term analytic philosophy roughly designates a group of philosophical methods that stress detailed argumentation, attention to semantics, use of classical logic and non-classical logics and clarity of meaning above all other criteria. Though the movement has broadened, it was a cohesive school in the first half of the century. Analytic philosophers were shaped strongly by logical positivism, united by the notion that philosophical problems could and should be solved by attention to logic and language.

Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore are also often counted as founders of analytic philosophy, beginning with their rejection of British idealism, their defense of realism and the emphasis they laid on the legitimacy of analysis. Russell's classic works The Principles of Mathematics,[77] On Denoting and Principia Mathematica with Alfred North Whitehead, aside from greatly promoting the use of mathematical logic in philosophy, set the ground for much of the research program in the early stages of the analytic tradition, emphasizing such problems as: the reference of proper names, whether 'existence' is a property, the nature of propositions, the analysis of definite descriptions, and discussions on the foundations of mathematics. These works also explored issues of ontological commitment and metaphysical problems regarding time, the nature of matter, mind, persistence and change, which Russell often tackled with the aid of mathematical logic.

Gottlob Frege's The Foundations of Arithmetic was the first analytic work, according to Michael Dummett (Origins of Analytical Philosophy). Frege took "the linguistic turn," analyzing philosophical problems through language. Some analytic philosophers held that philosophical problems arise through misuse of language or because of misunderstandings of the logic of human language.

In 1921, Ludwig Wittgenstein, who studied under Russell at Cambridge, published his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, which gave a rigidly "logical" account of linguistic and philosophical issues. Years later, he reversed a number of the positions he set out in the Tractatus, in for example his second major work, Philosophical Investigations (1953). Investigations was influential in the development of "ordinary language philosophy," which was promoted by Gilbert Ryle, J.L. Austin, and a few others.

In the United States, meanwhile, the philosophy of Quine was having a major influence, with the paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism. In that paper Quine criticizes the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements, arguing that a clear conception of analyticity is unattainable.

Patricia Churchland

Notable students of Quine include Donald Davidson and Daniel Dennett. The later work of Russell and the philosophy of Willard Van Orman Quine are influential exemplars of the naturalist approach dominant in the second half of the 20th century. But the diversity of analytic philosophy from the 1970s onward defies easy generalization: the naturalism of Quine and his epigoni was in some precincts superseded by a "new metaphysics" of possible worlds, as in the influential work of David Lewis. Recently, the experimental philosophy movement has sought to reappraise philosophical problems through social science research techniques.

Some influential figures in contemporary analytic philosophy are: Timothy Williamson, David Lewis, John Searle, Thomas Nagel, Hilary Putnam, Michael Dummett, Peter van Inwagen, Saul Kripke and Patricia Churchland.

Analytic philosophy has sometimes been accused of not contributing to the political debate or to traditional questions in aesthetics. However, with the appearance of A Theory of Justice by John Rawls and Anarchy, State, and Utopia by Robert Nozick, analytic political philosophy acquired respectability. Analytic philosophers have also shown depth in their investigations of aesthetics, with Roger Scruton, Nelson Goodman, Arthur Danto and others developing the subject to its current shape.

Continental

Continental philosophy is a set of 19th- and 20th-century philosophical traditions from mainland Europe. 20th-century movements such as German idealism, phenomenology, existentialism, modern hermeneutics, critical theory, structuralism, poststructuralism and others are included within this loose category. While identifying any non-trivial common factor in all these schools of thought is bound to be controversial, Michael E. Rosen has hypothesized a few common Continental themes: that the natural sciences cannot replace the human sciences; that the thinker is affected by the conditions of experience (one's place and time in history); that philosophy is both theoretical and practical; that metaphilosophy or reflection upon the methods and nature of philosophy itself is an important part of philosophy proper.

The founder of phenomenology, Edmund Husserl, sought to study consciousness as experienced from a first-person perspective, while Martin Heidegger drew on the ideas of Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Husserl to propose an unconventional existential approach to ontology. In the Arabic-speaking world, Arab nationalist philosophy became the dominant school of thought, involving philosophers such as Michel Aflaq, Zaki al-Arsuzi, Salah al-Din al-Bitar of Ba'athism and Sati' al-Husri.

Phenomenologically oriented metaphysics undergirded existentialism (Heidegger, Sartre, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Albert Camus) and finally poststructuralism (Gilles Deleuze, Jean-François Lyotard, Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida). The psychoanalytic work of Sigmund Freud, Jacques Lacan, Julia Kristeva, and others has also been influential in contemporary continental thought. Conversely, some philosophers have attempted to define and rehabilitate older traditions of philosophy. Most notably, Hans-Georg Gadamer and Alasdair MacIntyre have both, albeit in different ways, revived the tradition of Aristotelianism.

German idealism

Immanuel Kant

Transcendental idealism, advocated by Immanuel Kant, is the view that there are limits on what can be understood, since there is much that cannot be brought under the conditions of objective judgment. Kant wrote his Critique of Pure Reason (1781–1787) in an attempt to reconcile the conflicting approaches of rationalism and empiricism, and to establish a new groundwork for studying metaphysics. Although Kant held that objective knowledge of the world required the mind to impose a conceptual or categorical framework on the stream of pure sensory data—a framework including space and time themselves—he maintained that things-in-themselves existed independently of human perceptions and judgments; he was therefore not an idealist in any simple sense. Kant's account of things-in-themselves is both controversial and highly complex. Continuing his work, Johann Gottlieb Fichte and Friedrich Schelling dispensed with belief in the independent existence of the world, and created a thoroughgoing idealist philosophy.

The most notable work of this German idealism was G. W. F. Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, of 1807. Hegel admitted his ideas were not new, but that all the previous philosophies had been incomplete. His goal was to correctly finish their job. Hegel asserts that the twin aims of philosophy are to account for the contradictions apparent in human experience (which arise, for instance, out of the supposed contradictions between "being" and "not being"), and also simultaneously to resolve and preserve these contradictions by showing their compatibility at a higher level of examination ("being" and "not being" are resolved with "becoming"). This program of acceptance and reconciliation of contradictions is known as the "Hegelian dialectic".

Philosophers influenced by Hegel include Ludwig Andreas Feuerbach, who coined the term projection as pertaining to humans' inability to recognize anything in the external world without projecting qualities of ourselves upon those things; Karl Marx; Friedrich Engels; and the British idealists, notably T. H. Green, J. M. E. McTaggart and F. H. Bradley. Few 20th-century philosophers have embraced idealism. However, quite a few have embraced Hegelian dialectic. Immanuel Kant's "Copernican Turn" also remains an important philosophical concept today.

Phenomenology

Edmund Husserl

Edmund Husserl's phenomenology was an ambitious attempt to lay the foundations for an account of the structure of conscious experience in general.[78] An important part of Husserl's phenomenological project was to show that all conscious acts are directed at or about objective content, a feature that Husserl called intentionality.[79] Husserl published only a few works in his lifetime, which treat phenomenology mainly in abstract methodological terms; but he left an enormous quantity of unpublished concrete analyses. Husserl's work was immediately influential in Germany, with the foundation of phenomenological schools in Munich and Göttingen. Phenomenology later achieved international fame through the work of such philosophers as Martin Heidegger (formerly Husserl's research assistant), Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Jean-Paul Sartre. Through the work of Heidegger and Sartre, Husserl's focus on subjective experience influenced aspects of existentialism.

Existentialism

Existentialism is a term applied to the work of a number of late 19th- and 20th-century philosophers who, despite profound doctrinal differences,[80][81] shared the belief that philosophical thinking begins with the human subject—not merely the thinking subject, but the acting, feeling, living human individual.[82] In existentialism, the individual's starting point is characterized by what has been called "the existential attitude", or a sense of disorientation and confusion in the face of an apparently meaningless or absurd world.[83] Many existentialists have also regarded traditional systematic or academic philosophy, in both style and content, as too abstract and remote from concrete human experience.[84][85]

Søren Kierkegaard

Although they did not use the term, the 19th-century philosophers Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche are widely regarded as the fathers of existentialism. Their influence, however, has extended beyond existentialist thought.[86][87][88]

Structuralism and post-structuralism

Ferdinand de Saussure

Inaugurated by the linguist Ferdinand de Saussure, structuralism sought to clarify systems of signs through analyzing the discourses they both limit and make possible. Saussure conceived of the sign as being delimited by all the other signs in the system, and ideas as being incapable of existence prior to linguistic structure, which articulates thought. This led continental thought away from humanism, and toward what was termed the decentering of man: language is no longer spoken by man to express a true inner self, but language speaks man.

Structuralism sought the province of a hard science, but its positivism soon came under fire by poststructuralism, a wide field of thinkers, some of whom were once themselves structuralists, but later came to criticize it. Structuralists believed they could analyze systems from an external, objective standing, for example, but the poststructuralists argued that this is incorrect, that one cannot transcend structures and thus analysis is itself determined by what it examines. While the distinction between the signifier and signified was treated as crystalline by structuralists, poststructuralists asserted that every attempt to grasp the signified results in more signifiers, so meaning is always in a state of being deferred, making an ultimate interpretation impossible.

Structuralism came to dominate continental philosophy throughout the 1960s and early 1970s, encompassing thinkers as diverse as Claude Lévi-Strauss, Roland Barthes and Jacques Lacan. Post-structuralism came to predominate from the 1970s onwards, including thinkers such as Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Gilles Deleuze and even Roland Barthes; it incorporated a critique of structuralism's limitations.

Pragmatism

William James

Pragmatism asserts that the truth of beliefs consists in their usefulness and efficacy rather than their correspondence with reality.[89] Peirce and James were its co-founders and it was later modified by Dewey as instrumentalism. Since the usefulness of any belief at any time might be contingent on circumstance, Peirce and James conceptualised final truth as something established only by the future, final settlement of all opinion.[90]

Pragmatism attempted to find a scientific concept of truth that does not depend on personal insight (revelation) or reference to some metaphysical realm. It interpreted the meaning of a statement by the effect its acceptance would have on practice. Inquiry taken far enough is thus the only path to truth.[91]

For Peirce commitment to inquiry was essential to truth-finding, implied by the idea and hope that inquiry is not fruitless. The interpretation of these principles has been subject to discussion ever since. Peirce's maxim of pragmatism is, "Consider what effects, which might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object."[92]

Critics accused pragmatism falling victim to a simple fallacy: that because something that is true proves useful, that usefulness is an appropriate basis for its truthfulness.[93] Pragmatist thinkers include Dewey, Santayana, Quine and Lewis. Pragmatism was later worked on by Rorty, Lachs, Davidson, Haack and Putnam.


Other approaches

A variety of other academic and non-academic approaches have been explored.

Applied philosophy

Martin Luther King Jr

The ideas conceived by a society have profound repercussions on what actions the society performs. Weaver argued that ideas have consequences. Philosophy yields applications such as those in ethicsapplied ethics in particular—and political philosophy. The political and economic philosophies of Confucius, Sun Tzu, Chanakya, Ibn Khaldun, Ibn Rushd, Ibn Taymiyyah, Machiavelli, Leibniz, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill, Marx, Tolstoy, Gandhi and Martin Luther King, Jr. have been used to shape and justify governments and their actions. Progressive education as championed by Dewey had a profound impact on 20th century US educational practices. Descendants of this movement include efforts in philosophy for children, which are part of philosophy education. Clausewitz's political philosophy of war has had a profound effect on statecraft, international politics and military strategy in the 20th century, especially around World War II. Logic is important in mathematics, linguistics, psychology, computer science and computer engineering.

Other important applications can be found in epistemology, which aid in understanding the requisites for knowledge, sound evidence and justified belief (important in law, economics, decision theory and a number of other disciplines). The philosophy of science discusses the underpinnings of the scientific method and has affected the nature of scientific investigation and argumentation. Philosophy thus has fundamental implications for science as a whole. For example, the strictly empirical approach of B. F. Skinner's behaviorism affected for decades the approach of the American psychological establishment. Deep ecology and animal rights examine the moral situation of humans as occupants of a world that has non-human occupants to consider also. Aesthetics can help to interpret discussions of music, literature, the plastic arts and the whole artistic dimension of life. In general, the various philosophies strive to provide practical activities with a deeper understanding of the theoretical or conceptual underpinnings of their fields.

Philosophy and Society

Some of those who study philosophy become professional philosophers, typically by working as professors who teach, research and write in academic institutions.[94] However, most students of academic philosophy later contribute to law, journalism, religion, sciences, politics, business, or various arts.[26][95] For example, public figures who have degrees in philosophy include comedians Steve Martin and Ricky Gervais, filmmaker Terrence Malick, Pope John Paul II, Wikipedia co-founder Larry Sanger, Supreme Court Justice Stephen Bryer and vice presidential candidate Carly Fiorina.[96][97]

Professional philosophy

Germany was the first country to professionalize philosophy. At the end of 1817, Hegel was the first philosopher to be appointed Professor by the State, namely by the Prussian Minister of Education, as an effect of Napoleonic reform in Prussia. In the United States, the professionalisation grew out of reforms to the American higher-education system largely based on the German model.

Bertrand Russell

Within the last century, philosophy has increasingly become a professional discipline practiced within universities, like other academic disciplines. Accordingly, it has become less general and more specialized. In the view of one prominent recent historian: "Philosophy has become a highly organized discipline, done by specialists primarily for other specialists. The number of philosophers has exploded, the volume of publication has swelled, and the subfields of serious philosophical investigation have multiplied. Not only is the broad field of philosophy today far too vast to be embraced by one mind, something similar is true even of many highly specialized subfields."[98] Some philosophers argue that this professionalization has negatively affected the discipline.[99]

The end result of professionalization for philosophy has meant that work being done in the field is now almost exclusively done by university professors holding a doctorate in the field publishing in highly technical, peer-reviewed journals. While it remains common among the population at large for a person to have a set of religious, political or philosophical views that they consider their "philosophy", these views are rarely informed by or connected to the work being done in professional philosophy today. Furthermore, unlike many of the sciences for which there has come to be a healthy industry of books, magazines, and television shows meant to popularize science and communicate the technical results of a scientific field to the general populace, works by professional philosophers directed at an audience outside the profession remain rare. Philosopher Michael Sandel's book "Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?" and Harry Frankfurt's "On Bullshit" are examples of works that hold the uncommon distinction of having been written by professional philosophers but directed at and ultimately popular among a broader audience of non-philosophers. Both works became New York Times best sellers.

Non-professional philosophy

Many inquiries outside of academia are philosophical in the broad sense. Novelists, playwrights, filmmakers, and musicians, as well as scientists, social scientists, and others engage in recognizably philosophical activity.

Ayn Rand is the foremost example of an intellectual working contemporaneously with contemporary philosophy but whose contributions were not made within the professional discipline of "philosophy": "For all her [Ayn Rand's] popularity, however, only a few professional philosophers have taken her work seriously. As a result, most of the serious philosophical work on Rand has appeared in non-academic, non-peer-reviewed journals, or in books, and the bibliography reflects this fact."[15]

Also working from outside the profession were philosophers such as Gerd B. Achenbach (Die reine und die praktische Philosophie. Drei Vorträge zur philosophischen Praxis, 1983) and Michel Weber (see his Épreuve de la philosophie, 2008) who have proposed since the 1980s various forms of philosophical counseling claiming to bring Socratic dialogues back to life in a quasi-psychotherapeutic framework.

Pierre Hadot is famous for his analysis on the conception of philosophy during Greco-Roman antiquity. Hadot identified and analyzed the "spiritual exercises" used in ancient philosophy (influencing Michel Foucault's interest in such practices in the second and third volumes of his History of Sexuality). By "spiritual exercises" Hadot means "practices ... intended to effect a modification and a transformation in the subjects who practice them.[6] The philosophy teacher's discourse could be presented in such a way that the disciple, as auditor, reader, or interlocutor, could make spiritual progress and transform himself within."[7] Hadot shows that the key to understanding the original philosophical impulse is to be found in Socrates. What characterizes Socratic therapy above all is the importance given to living contact between human beings. Hadot's recurring theme is that philosophy in antiquity was characterized by a series of spiritual exercises intended to transform the perception, and therefore the being, of those who practice it; that philosophy is best pursued in real conversation and not through written texts and lectures; and that philosophy, as it is taught in universities today, is for the most part a distortion of its original, therapeutic impulse. He brings these concerns together in What Is Ancient Philosophy?,[7] which has been critically reviewed.[8]

Role of women

American philosopher of mind and philosopher of art Susanne Langer (1895–1985).

Although men have generally dominated philosophical discourse, women have engaged in philosophy throughout history. Women philosophers have contributed since ancient times–notably Hipparchia of Maroneia (active ca. 325 BC) and Arete of Cyrene (active 5th–4th century BC). More were accepted during the ancient, medieval and modern eras, but no women philosophers became part the Western canon until the 20th and 21st century, when some sources indicate that Susanne Langer, Hannah Arendt and Simone de Beauvoir entered the canon.[100][101]

In the early 1800s, some colleges and universities in the UK and US began admitting women, producing more female academics. Nevertheless, U.S. Department of Education reports from the 1990s indicate that few women ended up in philosophy, and that philosophy is one of the least gender-proportionate fields in the humanities.[102] In 2014, Inside Higher Education described the philosophy "...discipline's own long history of misogyny and sexual harassment" of women students and professors.[103]University of Sheffield philosophy professor Jennifer Saul stated in 2015 that women are "...leaving philosophy after being harassed, assaulted, or retaliated against." [104]

In the early 1990s, the Canadian Philosophical Association noted a gender imbalance and gender bias in the academic field of philosophy.[105] In June 2013, a US sociology professor stated that "out of all recent citations in four prestigious philosophy journals, female authors comprise just 3.6 percent of the total."[106] Susan Price argues that the philosophical "...canon remains dominated by white males—the discipline that...still hews to the myth that genius is tied to gender."[107] According to Saul, "[p]hilosophy, the oldest of the humanities, is also the malest (and the whitest). While other areas of the humanities are at or near gender parity, philosophy is actually more overwhelmingly male than even mathematics."[108]

In 2000, the Open Court Publishing Company began publishing a series of books on philosophy and popular culture. Each book consists of essays written by philosophers for general readers. The books "explore the meanings, concepts and puzzles within television shows, movies, music and other icons of popular culture"[109] analyzing topics such as the TV shows Seinfeld and The Simpsons, The Matrix and Star Wars movies and related media and new technological developments such as the iPod and Facebook. Their most recent publication (as of 2016) is titled Louis C.K. and Philosophy; its subject is the comedian Louis C.K..

The Matrix makes numerous references to philosophy including Buddhism, Vedanta, Advaita Hinduism, Christianity, Messianism, Judaism, Gnosticism, existentialism and nihilism. The film's premise resembles Plato's Allegory of the cave, Descartes's evil demon, Kant's reflections on the Phenomenon versus the Ding an sich, Zhuangzi's "Zhuangzi dreamed he was a butterfly", Marxist social theory and the brain in a vat thought experiment. Many references to Baudrillard's Simulacra and Simulation appear in the film, although Baudrillard himself considered this a misrepresentation.[110]

See also

Template:Wikipedia books

References

  1. ^ "Strong's Greek Dictionary 5385".
  2. ^ "Home : Oxford English Dictionary". oed.com.
  3. ^ "Online Etymology Dictionary". Etymonline.com. Retrieved 22 August 2010.
  4. ^ The definition of philosophy is: "1. orig., love of, or the search for, wisdom or knowledge 2. theory or logical analysis of the principles underlying conduct, thought, knowledge, and the nature of the universe". Webster's New World Dictionary (Second College ed.).
  5. ^ Jenny Teichmann and Katherine C. Evans, Philosophy: A Beginner's Guide (Blackwell Publishing, 1999), p. 1: "Philosophy is a study of problems which are ultimate, abstract and very general. These problems are concerned with the nature of existence, knowledge, morality, reason and human purpose."
  6. ^ A.C. Grayling, Philosophy 1: A Guide through the Subject (Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 1: "The aim of philosophical inquiry is to gain insight into questions about knowledge, truth, reason, reality, meaning, mind, and value."
  7. ^ Adler, Mortimer J. (28 March 2000). How to Think About the Great Ideas: From the Great Books of Western Civilization. Chicago, Ill.: Open Court. ISBN 978-0-8126-9412-3.
  8. ^ Quinton, Anthony, The ethics of philosophical practice, p. 666, Philosophy is rationally critical thinking, of a more or less systematic kind about the general nature of the world (metaphysics or theory of existence), the justification of belief (epistemology or theory of knowledge), and the conduct of life (ethics or theory of value). Each of the three elements in this list has a non-philosophical counterpart, from which it is distinguished by its explicitly rational and critical way of proceeding and by its systematic nature. Everyone has some general conception of the nature of the world in which they live and of their place in it. Metaphysics replaces the unargued assumptions embodied in such a conception with a rational and organized body of beliefs about the world as a whole. Everyone has occasion to doubt and question beliefs, their own or those of others, with more or less success and without any theory of what they are doing. Epistemology seeks by argument to make explicit the rules of correct belief formation. Everyone governs their conduct by directing it to desired or valued ends. Ethics, or moral philosophy, in its most inclusive sense, seeks to articulate, in rationally systematic form, the rules or principles involved. in Honderich 1995 harvnb error: multiple targets (2×): CITEREFHonderich1995 (help).
  9. ^ Greco, John, ed. (1 October 2011). The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-983680-2.
  10. ^ Glymour, Clark (10 April 2015). "Chapters 1–6". Thinking Things Through: An Introduction to Philosophical Issues and Achievements (2nd ed.). A Bradford Book. ISBN 978-0-262-52720-0.
  11. ^ "Contemporary Skepticism | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  12. ^ "The Internet Classics Archive | The Republic by Plato". classics.mit.edu. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  13. ^ "Free Will | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  14. ^ a b "Philosophy". www.etymonline.com. Online Etymological Dictionary. Retrieved 19 March 2016. The English word "philosophy" is first attested to c. 1300, meaning "knowledge, body of knowledge."
  15. ^ a b Lindberg 2007, p. 3.
  16. ^ Shapin, Steven (1 January 1998). The Scientific Revolution (1st ed.). University Of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-75021-7.
  17. ^ Briggle, Robert Frodeman and Adam. "When Philosophy Lost Its Way". Opinionator. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  18. ^ Sartwell, Crispin (1 January 2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Beauty (Spring 2014 ed.).
  19. ^ "PLATO, Hippias Major | Loeb Classical Library". Loeb Classical Library. Retrieved 27 April 2016.
  20. ^ Feyerabend, Paul; Hacking, Ian (11 May 2010). Against Method (4th ed.). Verso. ISBN 978-1-84467-442-8.
  21. ^ "Nozick, Robert: Political Philosophy | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  22. ^ "Rawls, John | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  23. ^ More, Thomas (8 May 2015). Utopia. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-11070-7.
  24. ^ "Merriam-Webster Dictionary". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 14 May 2016.
  25. ^ "Merriam-Webster Dictionary". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 14 May 2016.
  26. ^ a b "Why Study Philosophy? An Unofficial "Daily Nous" Affiliate". www.whystudyphilosophy.com. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
  27. ^ "Online Etymology Dictionary". etymonline.com.
  28. ^ Kant, Immanuel (21 May 2012). Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781107401068. Ancient Greek philosophy was divided into three branches of knowledge: natural science, ethics, and logic.
  29. ^ McGinn, Colin (8 December 1993). Problems in Philosophy: The Limits of Inquiry (1st ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-55786-475-8.
  30. ^ "Video & Audio: Why isn't there more progress in philosophy? – Metadata". www.sms.cam.ac.uk. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  31. ^ Brewer, Talbot (11 June 2011). The Retrieval of Ethics (1st ed.). Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-969222-4.
  32. ^ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich; Brown, Robert F. (1 January 2006). Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Greek philosophy. Clarendon Press. p. 33. ISBN 978-0-19-927906-7.
  33. ^ "Plato's "Symposium"". www.perseus.tufts.edu. p. 201d and following. Retrieved 22 April 2016.
  34. ^ Process and Reality p. 39
  35. ^ "A Taxonomy of Philosophy"
  36. ^ Kenny 2012.
  37. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (1 January 2014). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Religion and Science (Spring 2014 ed.).
  38. ^ G & C. Merriam Co. (1913). Webster's Revised Unabridged Dictionary (1913 ed.). G & C. Merriam Co. p. 501. Retrieved 13 May 2012. E*pis`te*mol"o*gy (?), n. [Gr. knowledge + -logy.] The theory or science of the method or grounds of knowledge. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |editors= ignored (|editor= suggested) (help)
  39. ^ Kelly (1998) p. ix
  40. ^ Review by Tom Riedel (Regis University)
  41. ^ "Merriam-Webster.com". Retrieved 21 August 2012.
  42. ^ Definition 1 of aesthetics from the Merriam-Webster Dictionary Online.
  43. ^ Zangwill, Nick. "Aesthetic Judgment", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 02-28-2003/10-22-2007. Retrieved 24 July 2008.
  44. ^ "aesthetic – definition of aesthetic in English from the Oxford dictionary". oxforddictionaries.com.
  45. ^ White, Curtis (5 August 2014). The Science Delusion: Asking the Big Questions in a Culture of Easy Answers. Brooklyn, N.Y.: Melville House. ISBN 9781612193908.
  46. ^ Carnap, Rudolf (1953). ""Inductive Logic and Science"". Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 80 (3): 189–97. doi:10.2307/20023651. JSTOR 20023651.
  47. ^ Cite error: The named reference encyclopedia was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  48. ^ Cite error: The named reference contemporaries was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  49. ^ Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy, Volume III: From Ockham to Suarez (The Newman Press, 1953) p. 18: "When one looks at Renaissance philosophy … one is faced at first sight with a rather bewildering assortment of philosophies."
  50. ^ Brian Copenhaver and Charles Schmitt, Renaissance Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1992), p. 4: "one may identify the hallmark of Renaissance philosophy as an accelerated and enlarged interest, stimulated by newly available texts, in primary sources of Greek and Roman thought that were previously unknown or partially known or little read."
  51. ^ Cite error: The named reference transmission was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  52. ^ Copleston, ibid.: "The bulk of Renaissance thinkers, scholars and scientists were, of course, Christians … but none the less the classical revival … helped to bring to the fore a conception of autonomous man or an idea of the development of the human personality, which, though generally Christian, was more 'naturalistic' and less ascetic than the mediaeval conception."
  53. ^ Cite error: The named reference intellectual was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  54. ^ Cite error: The named reference The Renaissance Philosophy of Man was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  55. ^ Cite error: The named reference Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy11 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  56. ^ Cite error: The named reference Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  57. ^ Diane Collinson. Fifty Major Philosophers, A Reference Guide. p. 125.
  58. ^ Cite error: The named reference philosophers was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  59. ^ Steven Nadler, A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, pp. 1–2: "By the seventeenth century […] it had become more common to find original philosophical minds working outside the strictures of the university—i.e., ecclesiastic—framework. […] by the end of the eighteenth century, [philosophy] was a secular enterprise."
  60. ^ Anthony Kenny, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3 (Oxford University Press, 2006), p. xii: "To someone approaching the early modern period of philosophy from an ancient and medieval background the most striking feature of the age is the absence of Aristotle from the philosophic scene."
  61. ^ Donald Rutherford, The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2006), p. 1: "epistemology assumes a new significance in the early modern period as philosophers strive to define the conditions and limits of human knowledge."
  62. ^ Kenny, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3, p. 211: "The period between Descartes and Hegel was the great age of metaphysical system-building."
  63. ^ Kenny, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3, pp. 179–180: "the seventeenth century saw the gradual separation of the old discipline of natural philosophy into the science of physics […] [b]y the nineteenth century physics was a fully mature empirical science, operating independently of philosophy."
  64. ^ Kenny, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3, pp. 212–331.
  65. ^ Nadler, A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, pp. 2–3: "Why should the early modern period in philosophy begin with Descartes and Bacon, for example, rather than with Erasmus and Montaigne? […] Suffice it to say that at the beginning of the seventeenth century, and especially with Bacon and Descartes, certain questions and concerns come to the fore—a variety of issues that motivated the inquiries and debates that would characterize much philosophical thinking for the next two centuries."
  66. ^ Rutherford, The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, p. 1: "Most often this [period] has been associated with the achievements of a handful of great thinkers: the so-called 'rationalists' (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz) and 'empiricists' (Locke, Berkeley, Hume), whose inquiries culminate in Kant's 'Critical philosophy.' These canonical figures have been celebrated for the depth and rigor of their treatments of perennial philosophical questions..."
  67. ^ Nadler, A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, p. 2: "The study of early modern philosophy demands that we pay attention to a wide variety of questions and an expansive pantheon of thinkers: the traditional canonical figures (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume), to be sure, but also a large 'supporting cast'..."
  68. ^ Cite error: The named reference philosophical13 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  69. ^ Cite error: The named reference rutherford was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  70. ^ Kenny, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 3, p. xiii.
  71. ^ Nadler, A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, p. 3.
  72. ^ Cite error: The named reference Shand was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  73. ^ Cite error: The named reference universities was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  74. ^ Cite error: The named reference frederick was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  75. ^ Cite error: The named reference transformation was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  76. ^ Nicholas Joll, http://www.iep.utm.edu/con-meta/
  77. ^ Cite error: The named reference russell was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  78. ^ Cite error: The named reference Ref-1 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  79. ^ Cite error: The named reference Dreyfus was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  80. ^ Cite error: The named reference existentialism was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  81. ^ Oxford Companion to Philosophy, ed. Ted Honderich, New York (1995), page 259.
  82. ^ Cite error: The named reference existentialism26 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  83. ^ Cite error: The named reference existentialism27 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  84. ^ Cite error: The named reference existentialism28 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  85. ^ Cite error: The named reference existentialism29 was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  86. ^ Cite error: The named reference kierkegaard was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  87. ^ Cite error: The named reference Bob was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  88. ^ Cite error: The named reference existentialists was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  89. ^ Cite error: The named reference Rorty was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  90. ^ Cite error: The named reference Putnam was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  91. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1878), "How to Make Our Ideas Clear", Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, 286–302. Reprinted often, including Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 388–410 and Essential Peirce v. 1, 124–41. See end of §II for the pragmatic maxim. See third and fourth paragraphs in §IV for the discoverability of truth and the real by sufficient investigation. Also see quotes from Peirce from across the years in the entries for "Truth" and "Pragmatism, Maxim of..." in the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, editors, University of Helsinki.
  92. ^ Cite error: The named reference paragraphs was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  93. ^ Cite error: The named reference Pratt was invoked but never defined (see the help page).
  94. ^ "Where Can Philosophy Take Me? | Philosophy". philosophy.as.uky.edu. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
  95. ^ Cropper, Carol Marie (26 December 1997). "Philosophers Find the Degree Pays Off in Life And in Work". The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
  96. ^ Marketing, Mansfield University Department of. "Famous Philosophy Majors | Mansfield University". www.mansfield.edu. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
  97. ^ W, Justin (8 December 2014). "Famous Philosophy Majors Poster (updated with new link)". Daily Nous. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
  98. ^ Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, vol. 2, p. 463.
  99. ^ "Socrates Tenured – Rowman & Littlefield International". www.rowmaninternational.com. Retrieved 25 April 2016.
  100. ^ Duran, Jane. Eight women philosophers: theory, politics, and feminism. University of Illinois Press, 2005.
  101. ^ "Why I Left Academia: Philosophy's Homogeneity Needs Rethinking – Hippo Reads".
  102. ^ "Salary, Promotion, and Tenure Status of Minority and Women Faculty in U.S. Colleges and Universities."National Center for Education Statistics, Statistical Analysis Report, March 2000; U.S. Department of Education, Office of Education Research and Improvement, Report # NCES 2000–173;1993 National Study of Postsecondary Faculty (NSOPF:93). See also "Characteristics and Attitudes of Instructional Faculty and Staff in the Humanities." National Center For Education Statistics, E.D. Tabs, July 1997. U.S. Department of Education, Office of Education Research and Improvement, Report # NCES 97-973;1993 National Study of Postsecondary Faculty (NSOPF-93).
  103. ^ "Unofficial Internet campaign outs professor for alleged sexual harassment, attempted assault".
  104. ^ Ratcliffe, Rebecca; Shaw, Claire (5 January 2015). "Philosophy is for posh, white boys with trust funds' – why are there so few women?".
  105. ^ "Women in Philosophy: Problems with the Discrimination Hypothesis - National Association of Scholars".
  106. ^ Sesardic, Neven; De Clercq, Rafael (2014). "Women in Philosophy: Problems with the Discrimination Hypothesis" (PDF). Academic Questions. New York: Springer Science+Business Media. doi:10.1007/s12129-014-9464-x.
  107. ^ Price, Susan. "Reviving the Female Canon".
  108. ^ http://www.salon.com/2013/08/15/philosophy_has_a_sexual_harassment_problem/
  109. ^ "Popular Culture and Philosophy". www.opencourtbooks.com. Retrieved 2 May 2016.
  110. ^ "IJBS". Web.archive.org. 21 October 2010. Archived from the original on 21 October 2010. Retrieved 11 July 2012. {{cite web}}: Unknown parameter |deadurl= ignored (|url-status= suggested) (help)

Sources

30em

Further reading

General introductions

  • Blumenau, Ralph. Philosophy and Living. ISBN 978-0-907845-33-1
  • Craig, Edward. Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-285421-6
  • Harrison-Barbet, Anthony, Mastering Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-333-69343-8
  • Russell, Bertrand. The Problems of Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-19-511552-9
  • Sinclair, Alistair J. What is Philosophy? An Introduction, 2008, ISBN 978-1-903765-94-4
  • Sober, Elliott. (2001). Core Questions in Philosophy: A Text with Readings. Upper Saddle River, Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-189869-1
  • Solomon, Robert C. Big Questions: A Short Introduction to Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-534-16708-0
  • Warburton, Nigel. Philosophy: The Basics. ISBN 978-0-415-14694-4
  • Nagel, Thomas. What Does It All Mean? A Very Short Introduction to Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-19-505292-3
  • Classics of Philosophy (Vols. 1, 2, & 3) by Louis P. Pojman
  • The English Philosophers from Bacon to Mill by Edwin Arthur
  • European Philosophers from Descartes to Nietzsche by Monroe Beardsley
  • Cottingham, John. Western Philosophy: An Anthology. 2nd ed. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub., 2008. Print. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies.
  • Tarnas, Richard. The Passion of the Western Mind: Understanding the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World View. ISBN 978-0-345-36809-6

Topical introductions

Eastern

  • A Source Book in Indian Philosophy by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, Charles A. Moore
  • Hamilton, Sue. Indian Philosophy: a Very Short Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-285374-5
  • Kupperman, Joel J. Classic Asian Philosophy: A Guide to the Essential Texts. ISBN 978-0-19-513335-6
  • Lee, Joe and Powell, Jim. Eastern Philosophy For Beginners. ISBN 978-0-86316-282-4
  • Smart, Ninian. World Philosophies. ISBN 978-0-415-22852-7
  • Copleston, Frederick. Philosophy in Russia: From Herzen to Lenin and Berdyaev. ISBN 978-0-268-01569-5

African

  • Imbo, Samuel Oluoch. '3'An Introduction to African Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-8476-8841-8

Islamic

Historical introductions

Ancient

  • Knight, Kelvin. Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre. ISBN 978-0-7456-1977-4

Medieval

Modern

  • Existentialism: Basic Writings (Second Edition) by Charles Guignon, Derk Pereboom
  • Curley, Edwin, A Spinoza Reader, Princeton, 1994, ISBN 978-0-691-00067-1
  • Bullock, Alan, R. B. Woodings, and John Cumming, eds. The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thinkers, in series, Fontana Original[s]. Hammersmith, Eng.: Fontana Press, 1992, cop. 1983. xxv, 867 p. ISBN 978-0-00-636965-3
  • Scruton, Roger. A Short History of Modern Philosophy. ISBN 978-0-415-26763-2

Contemporary

  • Contemporary Analytic Philosophy: Core Readings by James Baillie
  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony. Thinking it Through  – An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy, 2003, ISBN 978-0-19-513458-2
  • Critchley, Simon. Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. ISBN 978-0-19-285359-2

Reference works

  • Chan, Wing-tsit (1963). A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-01964-9. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Huang, Siu-chi (1999). Essentials of Neo-Confucianism: Eight Major Philosophers of the Song and Ming Periods. Greenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 0-313-26449-X. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Honderich, T., ed. (1995). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
  • The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy by Robert Audi
  • The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (10 vols.) edited by Edward Craig, Luciano Floridi (available online by subscription); or
  • The Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy edited by Edward Craig (an abridgement)
  • Edwards, Paul, ed. (1967). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Macmillan & Free Press. {{cite book}}: Unknown parameter |editorlink= ignored (|editor-link= suggested) (help); in 1996, a ninth supplemental volume appeared that updated the classic 1967 encyclopedia.
  • International Directory of Philosophy and Philosophers. Charlottesville, Philosophy Documentation Center.
  • Directory of American Philosophers. Charlottesville, Philosophy Documentation Center.
  • Routledge History of Philosophy (10 vols.) edited by John Marenbon
  • History of Philosophy (9 vols.) by Frederick Copleston
  • A History of Western Philosophy (5 vols.) by W. T. Jones
  • History of Italian Philosophy (2 vols.) by Eugenio Garin. Translated from Italian and Edited by Giorgio Pinton. Introduction by Leon Pompa.
  • Encyclopaedia of Indian Philosophies (8 vols.), edited by Karl H. Potter et al. (first 6 volumes out of print)
  • Indian Philosophy (2 vols.) by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan
  • A History of Indian Philosophy (5 vols.) by Surendranath Dasgupta
  • History of Chinese Philosophy (2 vols.) by Fung Yu-lan, Derk Bodde
  • Instructions for Practical Living and Other Neo-Confucian Writings by Wang Yang-ming by Chan, Wing-tsit
  • Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy edited by Antonio S. Cua
  • Encyclopedia of Eastern Philosophy and Religion by Ingrid Fischer-Schreiber, Franz-Karl Ehrhard, Kurt Friedrichs
  • Companion Encyclopedia of Asian Philosophy by Brian Carr, Indira Mahalingam
  • A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English by John A. Grimes
  • History of Islamic Philosophy edited by Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Oliver Leaman
  • History of Jewish Philosophy edited by Daniel H. Frank, Oliver Leaman
  • A History of Russian Philosophy: From the Tenth to the Twentieth Centuries by Valerii Aleksandrovich Kuvakin
  • Ayer, A.J. et al., Ed. (1994) A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations. Blackwell Reference Oxford. Oxford, Basil Blackwell Ltd.
  • Blackburn, S., Ed. (1996)The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
  • Mauter, T., Ed. The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy. London, Penguin Books.
  • Runes, D., Ed. (1942). The Dictionary of Philosophy. New York, The Philosophical Library, Inc.
  • Angeles, P.A., Ed. (1992). The Harper Collins Dictionary of Philosophy. New York, Harper Perennial.
  • Bunnin, Nicholas; Tsui-James, Eric, eds. (15 April 2008). The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-99787-1.
  • Hoffman, Eric, Ed. (1997) Guidebook for Publishing Philosophy. Charlottesville, Philosophy Documentation Center.
  • Popkin, R.H. (1999). The Columbia History of Western Philosophy. New York, Columbia University Press.
  • Bullock, Alan, and Oliver Stallybrass, jt. eds. The Harper Dictionary of Modern Thought. New York: Harper & Row, 1977. xix, 684 p. N.B.: "First published in England under the title, The Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thought." ISBN 978-0-06-010578-5
  • Reese, W. L. Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion: Eastern and Western Thought. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1980. iv, 644 p. ISBN 978-0-391-00688-1
Template:Wikibarphilo