Jump to content

Sentience: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Linking to the main article
where is a reference affirming this is a prevailing view? Why should we take Rasnaboy's word for these claims?
Line 4: Line 4:
'''Sentience''' is the capacity to be aware of [[feeling]]s and sensations.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/sentience|title=Definition of SENTIENCE|website=www.merriam-webster.com|language=en|access-date=2019-07-01}}</ref> Eighteenth-century philosophers used the concept to distinguish the ability to think (''[[reason]]'') from the ability to feel (''sentience''). In modern Western philosophy, sentience is the ability to experience [[sensation (psychology)|sensations]] (known in [[philosophy of mind]] as "[[qualia]]"). In Eastern philosophy, sentience is a metaphysical quality of all things that require respect and care.{{Citation needed|date=October 2020}}
'''Sentience''' is the capacity to be aware of [[feeling]]s and sensations.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/sentience|title=Definition of SENTIENCE|website=www.merriam-webster.com|language=en|access-date=2019-07-01}}</ref> Eighteenth-century philosophers used the concept to distinguish the ability to think (''[[reason]]'') from the ability to feel (''sentience''). In modern Western philosophy, sentience is the ability to experience [[sensation (psychology)|sensations]] (known in [[philosophy of mind]] as "[[qualia]]"). In Eastern philosophy, sentience is a metaphysical quality of all things that require respect and care.{{Citation needed|date=October 2020}}


The prevailing scientific view today declares sentience as that which requires specialized [[Nervous system|neural structures]], chiefly neuroanatomical, neurochemical, and neurophysiological substrates, which manifests in more complex organisms as the [[central nervous system]], to exhibit [[consciousness]] as stated in the [[Animal consciousness|Cambridge Declaration of Consciousness]], which was publicly proclaimed on 7 July 2012 at the [[Cambridge University]].{{Ref label|A|a|none}} Accordingly, only organisms that possess these substrates, all within the [[Kingdom Animalia|animal kingdom]], are said to be sentient.<ref name="CDC2012">{{cite web
Regarding animal consciousness, according to the [[Animal consciousness|Cambridge Declaration of Consciousness]], which was publicly proclaimed on 7 July 2012 at the [[Cambridge University]], [[Consciousness]] as that which requires specialized [[Nervous system|neural structures]], chiefly neuroanatomical, neurochemical, and neurophysiological substrates, which manifests in more complex organisms as the [[central nervous system]], to exhibit consciousness.{{Ref label|A|a|none}} Accordingly, only organisms that possess these substrates, all within the [[Kingdom Animalia|animal kingdom]], are said to be conscious. Sentience is not mentioned anywhere in this document,<ref name="CDC2012">{{cite web
| url = http://fcmconference.org/img/CambridgeDeclarationOnConsciousness.pdf
| url = http://fcmconference.org/img/CambridgeDeclarationOnConsciousness.pdf
| title = The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness
| title = The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness
Line 12: Line 12:
| website = FCM Conference
| website = FCM Conference
| publisher = Cambridge University
| publisher = Cambridge University
| access-date = 5 August 2020}}</ref> [[Sponge]]s, [[placozoa]]ns, and [[mesozoa]]ns, with simple body plans and no nervous system, are the only members of the animal kingdom that possess no sentience.{{Citation needed|date=October 2020}}
| access-date = 5 August 2020}}</ref> but according to Wikipedia editor 'Rasnaboy', either the scientists involved in this project were mistaken in their terminology and actually meant to make the declaration about 'sentience'. [[Sponge]]s, [[placozoa]]ns, and [[mesozoa]]ns, with simple body plans and no nervous system, are the only members of the animal kingdom that possess no sentience.{{Citation needed|date=October 2020}}


==Philosophy and sentience==
==Philosophy and sentience==

Revision as of 10:08, 31 January 2021

Sentience is the capacity to be aware of feelings and sensations.[1] Eighteenth-century philosophers used the concept to distinguish the ability to think (reason) from the ability to feel (sentience). In modern Western philosophy, sentience is the ability to experience sensations (known in philosophy of mind as "qualia"). In Eastern philosophy, sentience is a metaphysical quality of all things that require respect and care.[citation needed]

Regarding animal consciousness, according to the Cambridge Declaration of Consciousness, which was publicly proclaimed on 7 July 2012 at the Cambridge University, Consciousness as that which requires specialized neural structures, chiefly neuroanatomical, neurochemical, and neurophysiological substrates, which manifests in more complex organisms as the central nervous system, to exhibit consciousness.[a] Accordingly, only organisms that possess these substrates, all within the animal kingdom, are said to be conscious. Sentience is not mentioned anywhere in this document,[2] but according to Wikipedia editor 'Rasnaboy', either the scientists involved in this project were mistaken in their terminology and actually meant to make the declaration about 'sentience'. Sponges, placozoans, and mesozoans, with simple body plans and no nervous system, are the only members of the animal kingdom that possess no sentience.[citation needed]

Philosophy and sentience

In the philosophy of consciousness, sentience can refer to the ability of any entity to have subjective perceptual experiences, or as some philosophers refer to them, "qualia"[3]—in other words, the ability to have states that it feels like something to be in.[4] This is distinct from other features of the mind and consciousness, such as creativity, intelligence, sapience, self-awareness, and intentionality (the ability to have thoughts about something). Sentience is a minimalistic way of defining consciousness, which otherwise commonly and collectively describes sentience plus further features of the mind. These further features of consciousness may not be necessary for sentience, which rests on the capacity to feel sensations and emotions.[5]

Some philosophers, notably Colin McGinn, believe that the physical process causing sentience to happen will never be understood, a position known as "new mysterianism." They do not deny that most other aspects of consciousness are subject to scientific investigation but they argue that subjective experiences will never be explained; i.e., sentience is the only aspect of consciousness that cannot be explained. Other philosophers (such as Daniel Dennett) disagree, arguing that all aspects of consciousness will eventually be explained by science.[6]

Recognition paradox and relation to sapience

While it has been traditionally assumed that sentience and sapience are, in principle, independent of each other, there are criticisms of that assumption. One such criticism is about recognition paradoxes, one example of which is that an entity that cannot distinguish a spider from a non-spider cannot be arachnophobic. More generally, it is argued that since it is not possible to attach an emotional response to stimuli that cannot be recognized, emotions cannot exist independently of cognition that can recognize. The claim that precise recognition exists as specific attention to some details in a modular mind is criticized both with regard to data loss as a small system of disambiguating synapses in a module physically cannot make as precise distinctions as a bigger synaptic system encompassing the whole brain, and for energy loss as having one system for motivation that needs some built-in cognition to recognize anything anyway and another cognitive system for making strategies would cost more energy than integrating it all in one system that use the same synapses. Data losses inherent in all information transfer from more precise systems to less precise systems are also argued to make it impossible for any imprecise system to use a more precise system as an "emissary", as a less precise system would not be able to tell whether the outdata from the more precise system was in the interest of the less precise system or not.[7][8]

Empirical data on conditioned reflex precision

The original studies by Ivan Pavlov that showed that conditioned reflexes in human children are more discriminating than those in dogs, human children salivating only at ticking frequencies very close to those at which food was served while dogs drool at a wider range of frequencies, have been followed up in recent years with comparative studies on more species. It is shown that both brain size and brain-wide connectivity contribute to make perception more discriminating, as predicted by the theory of a brain-wide perception system but not by the theory of separate systems for emotion and cognition.[9]

Indian religions

Eastern religions including Hinduism, Buddhism, Sikhism, and Jainism recognise non-humans as sentient beings.[10] In Jainism and Hinduism, this is closely related to the concept of ahimsa, nonviolence toward other beings. In Jainism, all matter is endowed with sentience; there are five degrees of sentience, from one to five.[citation needed] Water, for example, is a sentient being of the first order, as it is considered to possess only one sense, that of touch. Man is considered a sentient being of the fifth order.

Sentience in Buddhism is the state of having senses. In Buddhism, there are six senses, the sixth being the subjective experience of the mind. Sentience is simply awareness prior to the arising of Skandha. Thus, an animal qualifies as a sentient being. According to Buddhism, sentient beings made of pure consciousness are possible. In Mahayana Buddhism, which includes Zen and Tibetan Buddhism, the concept is related to the Bodhisattva, an enlightened being devoted to the liberation of others. The first vow of a Bodhisattva states: "Sentient beings are numberless; I vow to free them."

Animal welfare, rights, and sentience

Some in the animal rights movement contend that the ability to experience pleasure and pain implies sentience. The documentary Earthlings argues that while animals do not have all the desires and ability to comprehend as do humans, they do share the desires for food and water, shelter and companionship, freedom of movement and avoidance of pain.[11][b]

Animal-welfare advocates typically argue that any sentient being is entitled, at a minimum, to protection from unnecessary suffering[citation needed], though animal-rights advocates may differ on what rights (e.g., the right to life) may be entailed by simple sentience. Sentiocentrism describes the theory that sentient individuals are the center of moral concern.

The 18th-century philosopher Jeremy Bentham compiled enlightenment beliefs in Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, and he included his own reasoning in a comparison between slavery and sadism toward animals:

The French have already discovered that the blackness of the skin is no reason why a human being should be abandoned without redress to the caprice of a tormentor [see Louis XIV's Code Noir]... What else is it that should trace the insuperable line? Is it the faculty of reason, or, perhaps, the faculty of discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison a more rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of a day, or a week, or even a month, old. But suppose the case were otherwise, what would it avail? the [sic] question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?[12]

In the 20th century, Princeton University professor Peter Singer argued that Bentham's conclusion is often dismissed by an appeal to a distinction that condemns human suffering but allows non-human suffering, typically "appeals" that are logical fallacies (unless the distinction is factual, in which case the appeal is just one logical fallacy, petitio principii). Because many of the suggested distinguishing features of humanity—high intelligence; highly complex language; etc.—are not present in marginal cases such as mute humans, young children, deaf humans, and mentally disabled humans, it appears that the only distinction is a prejudice based on species alone, which animal-rights supporters call speciesism—that is, differentiating humans from other animals purely on the grounds that they are human. His opponents accuse him of the same petitio principii.

Gary Francione also bases his abolitionist theory of animal rights, which differs significantly from Singer's, on sentience. He asserts that, "All sentient beings, humans or nonhuman, have one right: the basic right not to be treated as the property of others."[13]

Andrew Linzey, founder of the Oxford Centre for Animal Ethics in England, is known as a foremost international advocate for recognising animals as sentient beings in biblically based faith traditions. The Interfaith Association of Animal Chaplains encourages animal ministry groups to adopt a policy of recognising and valuing sentient beings.

In 1997 the concept of animal sentience was written into the basic law of the European Union. The legally binding protocol annexed to the Treaty of Amsterdam recognises that animals are "sentient beings", and requires the EU and its member states to "pay full regard to the welfare requirements of animals".

The laws of several states include certain invertebrates such as cephalopods (octopuses, squids) and decapod crustaceans (lobsters, crabs) in the scope of animal protection laws, implying that these animals are also judged capable of experiencing pain and suffering.[14][15]

Artificial intelligence

The term "sentience" is not used by major artificial intelligence textbooks and researchers.[16] It is sometimes used in popular accounts of AI to describe "human level or higher intelligence" (or artificial general intelligence).

Sentience quotient

The sentience quotient concept was introduced by Robert A. Freitas Jr. in the late 1970s.[17] It defines sentience as the relationship between the information processing rate of each individual processing unit (neuron), the weight/size of a single unit, and the total number of processing units (expressed as mass). It was proposed as a measure for the sentience of all living beings and computers from a single neuron up to a hypothetical being at the theoretical computational limit of the entire universe. On a logarithmic scale it runs from −70 up to +50.

See also

Notes

a. ^ Quote: "The absence of a neocortex does not appear to preclude an organism from experiencing affective states. Convergent evidence indicates that non-human animals have the neuroanatomical, neurochemical, and neurophysiological substrates of conscious states along with the capacity to exhibit intentional behaviors. Consequently, the weight of evidence indicates that humans are not unique in possessing the neurological substrates that generate consciousness. Non-human animals, including all mammals and birds, and many other creatures, including octopuses, also possess these neurological substrates."[2]

b. ^ Quote: "Granted, these animals do not have all the desires we humans have; granted, they do not comprehend everything we humans comprehend; nevertheless, we and they do have some of the same desires and do comprehend some of the same things. The desires for food and water, shelter and companionship, freedom of movement and avoidance of pain."[11]

References

  1. ^ "Definition of SENTIENCE". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2019-07-01.
  2. ^ a b Low, Philip (7 July 2012). "The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness" (PDF). FCM Conference. Cambridge University. Retrieved 5 August 2020.
  3. ^ Cole 1983
  4. ^ Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat?. The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435-450.
  5. ^ Damasio, Antonio (October 2001). "Fundamental feelings". Nature. 413 (6858): 781. doi:10.1038/35101669. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 11677584. S2CID 226085.
  6. ^ Ramsey, William (2013). "Eliminative Materialism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 ed.). Stanford University. Retrieved 19 June 2014.
  7. ^ A. D. Milner, M. D. Rugg (2013). "The Neuropsychology of Consciousness"
  8. ^ E T Mullin (2007). "The Creation of Sensation and the Evolution of Consciousness"
  9. ^ Catania, A.C. (June 7, 1994). "Query: Did Pavlov's research ring a bell?". Psycoloquy Newsletter
  10. ^ Shanta, Bhakti Niskama (September–October 2015). "Life and consciousness – The Vedāntic view". Communicative & Integrative Biology. 8 (5): e1085138. doi:10.1080/19420889.2015.1085138. PMC 4802748. PMID 27066168. 27066168.
  11. ^ a b Monson S (2005), "Earthlings".
  12. ^ Bentham, Jeremy (1879) [This edition first published 1823]. "Chapter XVII. Of the Limits of the Penal Branch of Jurisprudence". An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (A New Edition, corrected by the Author). Clarendon Press. p. 311 footnote.
  13. ^ Francione, Gary. Official blog
  14. ^ Science, policy and cultural implications of animal sentience, Compassion in World Farming
  15. ^ These animals are mentioned explicitly in the Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness as sentient beings. See Low, Philip, Jaak Panksepp, Diana Reiss, David Edelman, Bruno Van Swinderen, & Christof Koch (2012) Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness". University of Cambridge.Cambridge
  16. ^ See the four most popular AI textbooks (or Wikipedia's survey of their contents), none of which mention "sentience" at all:
  17. ^ Freitas, R.A. Jr. (April 1984). "Xenopsychology". Analog Science Fiction/Science Fact. 104: 41–53.

Further reading