Jump to content

Market anarchism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Removing duplicated sidebar
Be bold. Exchanging History sections wth Left-wing market anarchism; the bigger and more detailed History section should be here
Line 8: Line 8:
== History ==
== History ==
=== Mutualism ===
=== Mutualism ===
{{main|Mutualism (economic theory)}}
{{main article|Mutualism (economic theory)}}
[[File:Portrait of Pierre Joseph Proudhon 1865.jpg|thumb|200px|[[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], the first self-identified anarchist, supported a free-market anarchism called [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]]]]
[[File:Josiah Warren.jpg|thumb|left|[[Josiah Warren]], the first American anarchist, was an early mutualist]]
[[Josiah Warren]] is widely regarded as the first [[Anarchism in the United States|American anarchist]]<ref name=Slate>Palmer, Brian (2010-12-29) [http://www.slate.com/id/2279457/ What do anarchists want from us?], ''[[Slate.com]]''</ref> and the four-page weekly paper he edited during 1833, ''The Peaceful Revolutionist'', was the first [[Anarchism|anarchist]] periodical published,<ref name="bailie20">William Bailie, {{cite web|url=http://libertarian-labyrinth.org/warren/1stAmAnarch.pdf |title=Archived copy |accessdate=2013-06-17 |url-status=dead |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20120204155505/http://libertarian-labyrinth.org/warren/1stAmAnarch.pdf |archivedate=2012-02-04 }} ''Josiah Warren: The First American Anarchist — A Sociological Study'', Boston: Small, Maynard & Co., 1906, p. 20</ref> an enterprise for which he built his own printing press, cast his own type and made his own printing plates.<ref name="bailie20"/> Warren was a follower of [[Robert Owen]] and joined Owen's community at [[New Harmony, Indiana]]. Josiah Warren termed the phrase "[[cost the limit of price]]", with "cost" here referring not to monetary price paid but the labor one exerted to produce an item.<ref>"A watch has a cost and a value. The cost consists of the amount of labor bestowed on the mineral or natural wealth, in converting it into metals…". Warren, Josiah. ''Equitable Commerce''</ref> Therefore, "he proposed a system to pay people with certificates indicating how many hours of work they did. They could exchange the notes at local time stores for goods that took the same amount of time to produce".<ref name=Slate/> He put his theories to the test by establishing an experimental "labor for labor store" called the [[Cincinnati Time Store]] where trade was facilitated by notes backed by a promise to perform labor. The store proved successful and operated for three years after which it was closed so that Warren could pursue establishing colonies based on [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]]. These included [[Utopia, Ohio|Utopia]] and [[Utopian Community of Modern Times|Modern Times]]. Warren said that [[Stephen Pearl Andrews]]' ''The Science of Society'', published in 1852, was the most lucid and complete exposition of Warren's own theories.<ref>Charles A. Madison. "Anarchism in the United States". ''Journal of the History of Ideas'', Vol. 6, No. 1. (Jan., 1945), p. 53</ref> Catalan historian Xavier Diez report that the [[Intentional community|intentional communal]] experiments pioneered by Warren were influential in [[European individualist anarchism|European individualist anarchists]] of the late 19th and early 20th centuries such as [[Emile Armand]] and the [[intentional communities]] started by them.<ref name="tesisenxarxa.net">[http://www.tesisenxarxa.net/TESIS_UdG/AVAILABLE/TDX...//txdr1de2.pdf Xavier Diez. ''L'Anarquisme Individualista A Espanya 1923–1938''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110721040723/http://www.tesisenxarxa.net/TESIS_UdG/AVAILABLE/TDX...//txdr1de2.pdf |date=2011-07-21 }} p. 42</ref>
[[Mutualism (economic theory)|Mutualism]] began in 18th-century English and French labour movements before taking an anarchist form associated with [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]] in France and others in the United States.<ref>Wilbur, Shawn (2006). "More from the 1826 "Mutualist"?". "A member of a community". ''The Mutualist''. This 1826 series criticised [[Robert Owen]]'s proposals and has been attributed to a dissident Owenite, possibly from the Friendly Association for Mutual Interests of Valley Forge.</ref> Proudhon proposed [[spontaneous order]], whereby organisation emerges without central authority, a "positive anarchy" where order arises when everybody does "what he wishes and only what he wishes"<ref>Proudhon, ''Solution to the Social Problem'', ed. H. Cohen (New York: Vanguard Press, 1927), p. 45.</ref> and where "business transactions alone produce the social order".<ref>{{cite book|last=Proudhon|first=Pierre-Joseph|authorlink=Pierre-Joseph Proudhon|title=The Principle of Federation|url=https://archive.org/details/principleoffeder0000prou|url-access=registration|publisher=University of Toronto Press|location=Toronto|year=1979|isbn=0-8020-5458-7|quote=The notion of ''anarchy'' in politics is just as rational and positive as any other. It means that once industrial functions have taken over from political functions, then business transactions alone produce the social order.}}</ref> It is important to recognize that Proudhon distinguished between ideal political possibilities and practical governance. For this reason, much in contrast to some of his theoretical statements concerning ultimate spontaneous self-governance, Proudhon was heavily involved in French parliamentary politics and allied himself not with anarchist, but rather with socialist factions of workers movements and in addition to advocating state-protected charters for worker-owned cooperatives he also promoted certain nationalization schemes during his life of public service.


Mutualism is concerned with [[Reciprocity (cultural anthropology)|reciprocity]], [[Free association (Marxism and anarchism)|free association]], [[Voluntarism (philosophy)|voluntary contract]], [[federation]] and [[Monetary reform|credit and currency reform]]. According to the American mutualist [[William Batchelder Greene]], each worker in the mutualist system would receive "just and exact pay for his work; services equivalent in cost being exchangeable for services equivalent in cost, without profit or discount".<ref>Greene, William Batchelder (1875). "Communism versus Mutualism". ''Socialistic, Communistic, Mutualistic and Financial Fragments''. Boston: Lee & Shepard. "Under the mutual system, each individual will receive the just and exact pay for his work; services equivalent in cost being exchangeable for services equivalent in cost, without profit or discount; and so much as the individual laborer will then get over and above what he has earned will come to him as his share in the general prosperity of the community of which he is an individual member".</ref> Mutualism has been retrospectively characterised as ideologically situated between [[Individualist anarchism|individualist]] and [[Collectivist anarchism|collectivist]] forms of [[anarchism]].<ref>Avrich, Paul (1996). ''Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in America''. Princeton University Press. p. 6. {{ISBN|0-691-04494-5}}.</ref><ref>Miller, David, ed. (1991). ''Blackwell Encyclopaedia of Political Thought''. Blackwell Publishing. p. 11. {{ISBN|0-631-17944-5}}.</ref> Proudhon first characterised his goal as a "third form of society, the synthesis of communism and property".<ref>Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph (1840). ''[[What Is Property?]]''. Princeton, MA: Benjamin Tucker (1876). p. 281.</ref>
[[Mutualism (economic theory)|Mutualism]] began in 18th-century English and French labour movements before taking an anarchist form associated with [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]] in France and others in the United States.<ref>"A member of a community," ''The Mutualist''; this 1826 series criticised [[Robert Owen]]'s proposals, and has been attributed to a dissident Owenite, possibly from the Friendly Association for Mutual Interests of Valley Forge; [[Shawn Wilburn|Wilbur, Shawn]], 2006, "More from the 1826 "Mutualist"?".</ref> Proudhon proposed [[spontaneous order]], whereby organisation emerges without central authority, a "positive anarchy" where order arises when everybody does "what he wishes and only what he wishes"<ref>Proudhon, ''Solution to the Social Problem'', ed. H. Cohen (New York: Vanguard Press, 1927), p. 45.</ref> and where "business transactions alone produce the social order".<ref>{{cite book |last=Proudhon |first=Pierre-Joseph |authorlink=Pierre-Joseph Proudhon |title=The Principle of Federation |url=https://archive.org/details/principleoffeder0000prou |url-access=registration |publisher=University of Toronto Press |location=Toronto |year=1979 |isbn=0-8020-5458-7 |quote=The notion of ''anarchy'' in politics is just as rational and positive as any other. It means that once industrial functions have taken over from political functions, then business transactions alone produce the social order.}}</ref> It is important to recognize that Proudhon distinguished between ideal political possibilities and practical governance. For this reason, much in contrast to some of his theoretical statements concerning ultimate spontaneous self-governance, Proudhon was heavily involved in French parliamentary politics and allied himself not with Anarchist but Socialist factions of workers movements and in addition to advocating state-protected charters for worker-owned cooperatives, promoted certain nationalization schemes during his life of public service. Mutualist anarchism is concerned with [[Reciprocity (cultural anthropology)|reciprocity]], free association, voluntary contract, federation and credit and currency reform. According to the American mutualist [[William Batchelder Greene]], each worker in the mutualist system would receive "just and exact pay for his work; services equivalent in cost being exchangeable for services equivalent in cost, without profit or discount".<ref>"Communism versus Mutualism", ''Socialistic, Communistic, Mutualistic and Financial Fragments''. (Boston: Lee & Shepard, 1875) [[William Batchelder Greene]]: "Under the mutual system, each individual will receive the just and exact pay for his work; services equivalent in cost being exchangeable for services equivalent in cost, without profit or discount; and so much as the individual laborer will then get over and above what he has earned will come to him as his share in the general prosperity of the community of which he is an individual member."</ref> Mutualism has been retrospectively characterised as ideologically situated between individualist and collectivist forms of anarchism.<ref>Avrich, Paul. ''Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in America'', Princeton University Press 1996 {{ISBN|0-691-04494-5}}, p. 6<br />''Blackwell Encyclopaedia of Political Thought'', Blackwell Publishing 1991 {{ISBN|0-631-17944-5}}, p. 11.</ref> Proudhon first characterised his goal as a "third form of society, the synthesis of communism and property".<ref>Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. ''What Is Property?'' Princeton, MA: Benjamin R. Tucker, 1876. p. 281.</ref>

[[File:Pierre Joseph Proudhon.jpg|thumb|200px|[[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], the first self-identified [[Anarchism|anarchist]], supported a left-wing market anarchism called [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]]]]
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was a French activist and theorist, the founder of mutualist philosophy, an [[economist]] and a [[libertarian socialist]]. He was the first person to declare himself an [[wikt:anarchist|anarchist]]<ref>''The Dynamite Club'', [[John M. Merriman]], p. 42</ref> and is among its most influential theorists. He is considered by many to be the "father of anarchism".<ref>Daniel Guerin, ''Anarchism: From Theory to Practice'' (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970).</ref> He became a member of the [[French Parliament]] after the [[French Revolution of 1848|Revolution of 1848]], whereupon and thereafter he referred to himself as a [[federalist]].<ref>Binkley, Robert C. Realism and Nationalism 1852–1871. Read Books. p. 118</ref> Proudhon, who was born in [[Besançon]], was a printer who taught himself [[Latin]] in order to better print books in the language. His best-known assertion is that ''[[Property is Theft!]]'', contained in his first major work, ''[[What Is Property?|What is Property? Or, an Inquiry into the Principle of Right and Government]]'' (''Qu'est-ce que la propriété? Recherche sur le principe du droit et du gouvernement''), published in 1840. The book's publication attracted the attention of the French authorities. It also attracted the scrutiny of [[Karl Marx]], who started a correspondence with its author. The two influenced each other: they met in Paris while Marx was exiled there. Their friendship finally ended when Marx responded to Proudhon's ''[[The System of Economic Contradictions, or The Philosophy of Poverty]]'' with the provocatively titled ''[[The Poverty of Philosophy]]''. The dispute became one of the sources of the split between the anarchist and [[Marxian economics|Marxian]] wings of the [[International Working Men's Association]]. Some, such as [[Edmund Wilson]], have contended that Marx's attack on Proudhon had its origin in the latter's defense of [[Karl Grün]], whom Marx bitterly disliked but who had been preparing translations of Proudhon's work. Proudhon favored [[Workers' council|workers' associations]] or [[co-operatives]] as well as individual worker/peasant possession over private ownership or the [[nationalization]] of land and workplaces. He considered [[social revolution]] to be achievable in a peaceful manner. In ''The Confessions of a Revolutionary'' Proudhon asserted that, ''Anarchy is Order Without Power'', the phrase which much later inspired, in the view of some, the anarchist ''[[Anarchist symbolism#Circle-A|circled-A]]'' symbol, today "one of the most common graffiti on the urban landscape".<ref>Marshall, Peter. [[Demanding the Impossible]]. Fontana, London. 1993. p. 558</ref> He unsuccessfully tried to create a [[national bank]] to be funded by what became an abortive attempt at an [[income tax]] on [[capitalists]] and [[shareholder]]s. Similar in some respects to a [[credit union]], it would have given interest-free [[loans]].<ref>Martin, Henri, & Alger, Abby Langdon. A Popular History of France from the First Revolution to the Present Time. D. Estes and C.E. Lauria. p. 189</ref>

[[William Batchelder Greene]] was a 19th-century [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualist]] [[individualist anarchist]], [[Unitarianism|Unitarian]] minister, soldier and promoter of [[free banking]] in the [[United States]]. Greene is best known for the works ''Mutual Banking''(1850), which proposed an interest-free banking system, and ''Transcendentalism'', a critique of the [[Transcendentalism|New England philosophical school]]. American anarchist historian Eunice Minette Schuster states: "It is apparent that [[Proudhon]]ian Anarchism was to be found in the United States at least as early as 1848 and that it was not conscious of its affinity to the Individualist Anarchism of [[Josiah Warren]] and [[Stephen Pearl Andrews]]. William B. Greene presented this Proudhonian Mutualism in its purest and most systematic form".<ref name="againstallauthority.org">[http://www.againstallauthority.org/NativeAmericanAnarchism.html ''Native American Anarchism: A Study of Left-Wing American Individualism'' by Eunice Minette Schuster] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160213201445/http://www.againstallauthority.org/NativeAmericanAnarchism.html |date=2016-02-13 }}</ref> After 1850, he became active in labor reform<ref name="againstallauthority.org"/> and was elected vice-president of the New England Labor Reform League, the majority of the members holding to Proudhon's scheme of mutual banking. In 1869, he was elected president of the Massachusetts Labor Union.<ref name="againstallauthority.org"/> Greene then published ''Socialistic, Mutualistic, and Financial Fragments'' (1875).<ref name="againstallauthority.org"/> He saw mutualism as the synthesis of "liberty and order".<ref name="againstallauthority.org"/> His "associationism is checked by individualism. 'Mind your own business,' "Judge not that ye be not judged". Over matters which are purely personal, as for example moral conduct, the individual is sovereign, as well as over that which he himself produces. For this reason he demands "mutuality" in marriage – the equal right of a woman to her own personal freedom and property".<ref name="againstallauthority.org"/>


=== Individualist anarchism in the United States ===
=== Individualist anarchism in the United States ===
{{main|Individualist anarchism in the United States}}
{{main article|Individualist anarchism in the United States}}
[[File:BenjaminTucker.jpg|thumb|left|200px|[[American individualist anarchist]] [[Benjamin Tucker]], known for his [[libertarian]] journal ''[[Liberty (1881–1908)|Liberty]]'', abandoned the [[natural rights]] conception of [[property rights]] in free-market anarchism for a [[Philosophy of Max Stirner|Stirnerite]] [[Egoist anarchism|egoism]]]]
[[Individualist anarchism in the United States|American individualist anarchist]] [[Benjamin Tucker]] identified as a socialist<ref>Tucker, Benjamin (1897). "[http://praxeology.net/BT-SSA.htm State Socialism and Anarchism: How Far They Agree and Wherein They Differ]." ''Instead of a Book: By a Man Too Busy to Write One''. New York</ref> and argued that the elimination of what he called the four monopolies—the land monopoly, the money and banking monopoly, the monopoly powers conferred by patents and the quasi-monopolistic effects of tariffs—would undermine the power of the wealthy and big business, making possible widespread property ownership and higher incomes for ordinary people while minimizing the power of would-be bosses and achieving socialist goals without state action. Tucker influenced and interacted with anarchist contemporaries—including [[Lysander Spooner]], [[Voltairine de Cleyre]], [[Dyer D. Lum]] and [[William B. Greene]]—who have in various ways influenced later left-libertarian thinking.<ref>On the nineteenth-century American individualist anarchists, see [[James J. Martin]], ''Men against the State: The Expositors of Individualist Anarchism in America'' (Colorado Springs, CO: Myles 1970).</ref>
A form of individualist anarchism was found in the United States as advocated by the Boston anarchists.<ref name=levy>Levy, Carl. "[http://uk.encarta.msn.com/encyclopedia_761568770_1/Anarchism.html Anarchism]". Microsoft [[Encarta]] Online Encyclopedia 2007. [https://www.webcitation.org/query?id=1257007798263485 Archived] 2009-10-31.</ref> Some Boston anarchists, including [[Benjamin Tucker]] and [[Lysander Spooner]], identified themselves as [[socialist]]s, a term often used in the 19th century in the sense of a commitment to improving conditions of the working class (i.e. the [[labor problem]]).<ref>Brooks, Frank H. 1994. ''The Individualist Anarchists: An Anthology of Liberty'' (1881–1908). Transaction Publishers. p. 75.</ref> The Boston anarchists such as Tucker and his followers are also considered socialists due to their opposition to usury.<ref>[http://www.infoshop.org/page/AnarchistFAQSectionG1#secg14 "G.1.4 Why is the social context important in evaluating Individualist Anarchism?" in ''An Anarchist FAQ'']{{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130315000327/http://www.infoshop.org/page/AnarchistFAQSectionG1#secg14 |date=March 15, 2013 }}</ref><ref>Stanford, Jim. Economics for Everyone: A Short Guide to the Economics of Capitalism. Ann Arbor: MI., Pluto Press. 2008. p. 36.</ref> By around the start of the 20th century, the heyday of individualist anarchism had passed,<ref>[[Paul Avrich|Avrich, Paul]]. 2006. ''Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in America''. [[AK Press]]. p. 6.</ref> On the other hand, anarchist historian [[George Woodcock]] describes Spooner's essays as an "eloquent elaboration" of [[Josiah Warren]] and the early American development of Proudhon's ideas and associates his works with that of [[Stephen Pearl Andrews]].<ref name="Woodcock 434">{{cite book|last=Woodcock|first=G.|authorlink=George Woodcock|title=Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements|year=1962|publisher=Penguin|location=Melbourne|page=434}}</ref> Woodcock also reports that both Spooner and Greene had been members of the [[socialist]] [[First International]].<ref name="Woodcock 460">{{cite book|last=Woodcock|first=G.|authorlink=George Woodcock|title=Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements|year=1962|publisher=Penguin|location=Melbourne|page=460}}</ref>

American individualist anarchist Benjamin Tucker identified as a socialist<ref>Tucker, Benjamin (1897). "[http://praxeology.net/BT-SSA.htm State Socialism and Anarchism: How Far They Agree and Wherein They Differ]." ''Instead of a Book: By a Man Too Busy to Write One''. New York</ref> and argued that the elimination of what he called the four monopolies, namely the land monopoly, the money and banking monopoly, the monopoly powers conferred by patents and the quasi-monopolistic effects of tariffs, would undermine the power of the wealthy and big business, making possible widespread property ownership and higher incomes for ordinary people, while minimizing the power of would-be bosses and achieving socialist goals without state action. Tucker influenced and interacted with anarchist contemporaries, including Spooner, [[Voltairine de Cleyre]], [[Dyer D. Lum]], and [[William B. Greene]], who have in various ways influenced later left-libertarian thinking.<ref>On the nineteenth-century American individualist anarchists, see [[James J. Martin]], ''Men against the State: The Expositors of Individualist Anarchism in America'' (Colorado Springs, CO: Myles 1970).</ref> [[Kevin Carson]] characterizes American individualist anarchism by saying: "Unlike the rest of the [[socialist]] movement, the individualist anarchists believed that the natural wage of labor in a free market was its product and that economic exploitation could only take place when capitalists and landlords harnessed the power of the state in their interests. Thus, individualist anarchism was an alternative both to the increasing statism of the mainstream socialist movement and to a liberal movement that was moving toward a mere apologetic for the power of big business.<ref>Kevin Carson. ''Organization Theory: A Libertarian Perspective''. BOOKSURGE. 2008. p. 1</ref> Two individualist anarchists who wrote in Benjamin Tucker's ''[[Liberty (1881–1908)|Liberty]]'' were also important labor organizers of the time. [[Joseph Labadie]] and [[Dyer Lum]]. [[Kevin Carson]] has praised [[Dyer Lum]]'s fusion of individualist ''[[laissez-faire]]'' economics with radical labor activism as "creative" and described him as "more significant than any in the Boston group".<ref name="Carson">Carson, Kevin. "May Day Thoughts: Individualist Anarchism and the Labor Movement". Mutualist Blog: Free Market Anti-Capitalism.</ref>

Some of the American individualist anarchists later in this era such as Benjamin Tucker abandoned [[natural rights]] positions and converted to [[Max Stirner]]'s [[egoist anarchism]]. Rejecting the idea of moral rights, Tucker said that there were only two rights, "the right of might" and "the right of contract". He also said after converting to egoist individualism: "In times past it was my habit to talk glibly of the right of man to land. It was a bad habit, and I long ago sloughed it off. Man's only right to land is his might over it".<ref>Tucker, Instead of a Book, p. 350</ref> In adopting Stirnerite egoism in 1886, Tucker rejected natural rights which had long been considered the foundation of libertarianism. This rejection galvanized the movement into fierce debates, with the natural rights proponents accusing the egoists of destroying libertarianism itself. So bitter was the conflict that a number of natural rights proponents withdrew from the pages of ''Liberty'' in protest even though they had hitherto been among its frequent contributors. Thereafter, ''Liberty'' championed egoism although its general content did not change significantly.<ref>[[Wendy McElroy]], [http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php%3Ftitle=1300&layout=html#chapter_100896 "Benjamin Tucker, Individualism, & Liberty: Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order"]</ref>

=== Geolibertarianism ===
{{main article|Geolibertarianism}}
[[File:Henry George.jpg|thumb|[[Henry George]], whose economic positions known as [[geoism]] existed within [[European individualist anarchism]]]]
[[Geolibertarianism]], an anarchist form of [[Henry George]]'s philosophy called [[geoism]], is considered left-libertarian because it assumes land to be initially owned in common, so that when land is privately appropriated the proprietor pays rent to the community.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.anti-state.com/geo/foldvary1.html |title=Geoanarchism by Fred Foldvary |publisher=Anti-state.com |date=2001-07-15 |accessdate=2013-03-26}}</ref> Geolibertarians generally advocate distributing the land rent to the community via a [[land value tax]] as proposed by Henry George and others before him. For this reason, they are often called "single taxers". [[Fred E. Foldvary]] coined the word geo-libertarianism in an article so titled in ''Land and Liberty''.<ref>May/June 1981, pp. 53–55.</ref> In the case of geoanarchism, the voluntary form of geolibertarianism as described by Foldvary, rent would be collected by private associations with the opportunity to secede from the rent-sharing community and not receive the community's services.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.anti-state.com/geo/foldvary1.html|title=Geoanarchism|authorlink=Fred E. Foldvary|first=Fred E.|last=Foldvary|accessdate=2009-04-15|date=2001-07-15|publisher=anti-state.com}}</ref>

Similar economic positions also existed within [[European individualist anarchism]]. [[Individualist anarchism in France|French individualist anarchist]] [[Émile Armand]] shows clearly opposition to capitalism and centralized economies when he said that the individualist anarchist "inwardly he remains refractory – fatally refractory – morally, intellectually, economically (The capitalist economy and the directed economy, the speculators and the fabricators of single are equally repugnant to him.)".<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.spaz.org/~dan/individualist-anarchist/library/emile-armand/life-activity.html |title="Anarchist Individualism as a Life and Activity" by Emile Armand |publisher=Spaz.org |date=2002-03-01 |accessdate=2013-10-11}}</ref> He argued for a pluralistic economic logic when he said: "Here and there everything happening – here everyone receiving what they need, there each one getting whatever is needed according to their own capacity. Here, [[Gift economy|gift]] and [[barter]] – one product for another; there, exchange – product for representative value. Here, the producer is the owner of the product, there, the product is put to the possession of the collectivity".<ref name="Armand">[http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/emile-armand-anarchist-individualism-and-amorous-comradeship#toc19 Émile Armand. ''Anarchist Individualism and Amorous Comradeship'']</ref>

Spanish individualist anarchist [[Miguel Gimenez Igualada]] thought that "capitalism is an effect of government; the disappearance of government means capitalism falls from its pedestal vertiginously. That which we call capitalism is not something else but a product of the State, within which the only thing that is being pushed forward is profit, good or badly acquired. And so to fight against capitalism is a pointless task, since be it [[State capitalism]] or Enterprise capitalism, as long as Government exists, exploiting capital will exist. The fight, but of consciousness, is against the State".<ref>"el capitalismo es sólo el efecto del gobierno; desaparecido el gobierno, el capitalismo cae de su pedestal vertiginosamente.... Lo que llamamos capitalismo no es otra cosa que el producto del Estado, dentro del cual lo único que se cultiva es la ganancia, bien o mal habida. Luchar, pues, contra el capitalismo es tarea inútil, porque sea Capitalismo de Estado o Capitalismo de Empresa, mientras el Gobierno exista, existirá el capital que explota. La lucha, pero de conciencias, es contra el Estado."[http://www.kclibertaria.comyr.com/lpdf/l125.pdf ''Anarquismo'' by Miguel Gimenez Igualada]</ref> His view on class division and [[technocracy]] are as follows: "Since when no one works for another, the profiteer from wealth disappears, just as government will disappear when no one pays attention to those who learned four things at universities and from that fact they pretend to govern men. Big industrial enterprises will be transformed by men in big associations in which everyone will work and enjoy the product of their work. And from those easy as well as beautiful problems anarchism deals with and he who puts them in practice and lives them are anarchists. The priority which without rest an anarchist must make is that in which no one has to exploit anyone, no man to no man, since that non-exploitation will lead to the limitation of property to individual needs".<ref>"¿La propiedad? ¡Bah! No es problema. Porque cuando nadie trabaje para nadie, el acaparador de la riqueza desaparece, como ha de desaparecer el gobierno cuando nadie haga caso a los que aprendieron cuatro cosas en las universidades y por ese sólo hecho pretenden gobernar a los hombres. Porque si en la tierra de los ciegos el tuerto es rey, en donde todos ven y juzgan y disciernen, el rey estorba. Y de lo que se trata es de que no haya reyes porque todos sean hombres. Las grandes empresas industriales las transformarán los hombres en grandes asociaciones donde todos trabajen y disfruten del producto de su trabajo. Y de esos tan sencillos como hermosos problemas trata el anarquismo y al que lo cumple y vive es al que se le llama anarquista...El hincapié que sin cansancio debe hacer el anarquista es el de que nadie debe explotar a nadie, ningún hombre a ningún hombre, porque esa no-explotación llevaría consigo la limitación de la propiedad a las necesidades individuales."[http://www.kclibertaria.comyr.com/lpdf/l125.pdf ''Anarquismo'' by Miguel Gimenez Igualada]</ref>


=== Alliance between libertarians and the New Left ===
=== Alliance between American libertarians and the New Left ===
{{libertarianism in the United States sidebar}}
The doyen of modern American market-oriented libertarianism, [[Austrian School]] economist [[Murray Rothbard]], was initially an enthusiastic partisan of the [[Old Right (United States)|Old Right]], particularly because of its general opposition to war and imperialism.<ref>Raimond, Justin (2001). ''An Enemy of the State: The Life of Murray N. Rothbard''. Amherst, NY: Prometheus.</ref> However, Rothbard had long embraced a reading of American history that emphasized the role of elite privilege in shaping legal and political institutions—one that was naturally agreeable to many on the left—and came increasingly in the 1960s to seek alliances on the left—especially with members of the [[New Left]]—in light of the [[Vietnam War]],<ref>Raimondo, pp. 151–209.</ref> the [[military draft]] and the emergence of the [[Black Power movement]].<ref>Doherty, Brian M. (2007). ''Radicals for Capitalism: A Freewheeling History of the Modern American Libertarian Movement''. New York: Public Affairs. p. 338.</ref>
The doyen of modern American market-oriented libertarianism, [[Austrian School]] economist [[Murray Rothbard]], was initially an enthusiastic partisan of the [[Old Right (United States)|Old Right]], particularly because of its general opposition to war and imperialism.<ref>Raimond, Justin (2001). ''An Enemy of the State: The Life of Murray N. Rothbard''. Amherst, NY: Prometheus.</ref> However, Rothbard had long embraced a reading of American history that emphasized the role of elite privilege in shaping legal and political institutions—one that was naturally agreeable to many on the left—and came increasingly in the 1960s to seek alliances on the left—especially with members of the [[New Left]]—in light of the [[Vietnam War]],<ref>Raimondo, pp. 151–209.</ref> the [[military draft]] and the emergence of the [[Black Power movement]].<ref>Doherty, Brian M. (2007). ''Radicals for Capitalism: A Freewheeling History of the Modern American Libertarian Movement''. New York: Public Affairs. p. 338.</ref>


Line 28: Line 46:
== Left-wing market anarchism ==
== Left-wing market anarchism ==
{{main|Left-wing market anarchism}}
{{main|Left-wing market anarchism}}
Left-wing market anarchism is a contemporary school of [[left-libertarianism]] and a revival of the free-market anarchist theories of mutualism and 19th century individualst anarchism. It is associated with scholars such as [[Kevin Carson]],<ref>Carson, Kevin A. (2008). ''Organization Theory: A Libertarian Perspective''. Charleston, SC:BookSurge.</ref><ref>Carson, Kevin A. (2010). ''The Homebrew Industrial Revolution: A Low-Overhead Manifesto''. Charleston, SC: BookSurge.</ref> [[Roderick T. Long]],<ref>Long, Roderick T. (2000). ''Reason and Value: Aristotle versus Rand''. Washington, D.C.: Objectivist Center</ref><ref>Long, Roderick T. (2008). [http://en.liberalis.pl/2008/01/04/interview-with-roderick-long/ "An Interview With Roderick Long"].</ref> Charles W. Johnson,<ref>Johnson, Charles W. (2008). [http://radgeek.com/gt/2010/03/02/liberty-equality-solidarity-toward-a-dialectical-anarchism/ "Liberty, Equality, Solidarity: Toward a Dialectical Anarchism"]. ''Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country?''. In Long, Roderick T.; Machan, Tibor. Aldershot: Ashgate pp. 155–188.</ref> [[Samuel Edward Konkin III]],<ref>Konkin III, Samuel Edward. ''[http://agorism.info/docs/NewLibertarianManifesto.pdf The New Libertarian Manifesto]''.</ref> Sheldon Richman,<ref name="LibertarianLeft"/><ref>Richman, Sheldon (18 December 2009). [http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/tgif/workers-of-the-world-unite "Workers of the World Unite for a Free Market"]. {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140722145233/http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/tgif/workers-of-the-world-unite|date=22 July 2014}}. Foundation for Economic Education.</ref><ref name="LibertarianLeft"/> [[Chris Matthew Sciabarra]]<ref>Sciabarra, Chris Matthew (2000). ''Total Freedom: Toward a Dialectical Libertarianism''. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.</ref> and [[Gary Chartier]],<ref>Chartier, Gary (2009). ''Economic Justice and Natural Law''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.</ref> who stress the value of radically free markets, termed [[freed market]]s to distinguish them from the common conception which these libertarians believe to be riddled with statist and capitalist privileges.<ref name="marketsnotcap">Gillis, William (2011). "The Freed Market". In Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. ''Markets Not Capitalism''. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 19–20.</ref> Referred to as left-wing market anarchists<ref>Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). ''Markets Not Capitalism''. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 1–16.</ref> or market-oriented left-libertarians,<ref name="LibertarianLeft"/> proponents of this approach strongly affirm the [[classical liberal]] ideas of [[self-ownership]] and [[free markets]] while maintaining that taken to their logical conclusions these ideas support strongly [[anti-capitalist]], [[Anti-corporatism|anti-corporatist]], anti-[[hierarchical]] and [[pro-labor]] positions in economics; [[anti-imperialism]] in foreign policy; and thoroughly [[Cultural liberalism|liberal]] or [[Civil libertarianism|radical]] views regarding cultural issues as such as gender, sexuality and race. This strand of left-libertarianism tends to be rooted either in the [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualist economics]] conceptualized by [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], [[American individualist anarchism]], or in a [[left-wing]] interpretation or extension of the thought of [[Murray Rothbard]]. According to libertarian scholar Sheldon Richman: {{quote|Left-libertarians favor worker solidarity vis-à-vis bosses, support poor people's [[squatting]] on government or abandoned property, and prefer that corporate privileges be repealed before the regulatory restrictions on how those privileges may be exercised. They see [[Walmart]] as a symbol of corporate favoritism—supported by highway subsidies and eminent domain—view the fictive personhood of the [[Limited liability company|limited-liability corporation]] with suspicion, and doubt that [[Third World]] [[sweatshop]]s would be the "best alternative" in the absence of government manipulation. Left-libertarians tend to eschew electoral politics, having little confidence in strategies that work through the government. They prefer to develop alternative institutions and methods of working around the state.<ref name="LibertarianLeft"/>}}
{{libertarian socialism sidebar}}
Another contemporary school of [[left-libertarianism]] is associated with scholars such as [[Kevin Carson]],<ref>Carson, Kevin A. (2008). ''Organization Theory: A Libertarian Perspective''. Charleston, SC:BookSurge.</ref><ref>Carson, Kevin A. (2010). ''The Homebrew Industrial Revolution: A Low-Overhead Manifesto''. Charleston, SC: BookSurge.</ref> [[Roderick T. Long]],<ref>Long, Roderick T. (2000). ''Reason and Value: Aristotle versus Rand''. Washington, D.C.: Objectivist Center</ref><ref>Long, Roderick T. (2008). [http://en.liberalis.pl/2008/01/04/interview-with-roderick-long/ "An Interview With Roderick Long"].</ref> Charles W. Johnson,<ref>Johnson, Charles W. (2008). [http://radgeek.com/gt/2010/03/02/liberty-equality-solidarity-toward-a-dialectical-anarchism/ "Liberty, Equality, Solidarity: Toward a Dialectical Anarchism"]. ''Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country?''. In Long, Roderick T.; Machan, Tibor. Aldershot: Ashgate pp. 155–188.</ref> [[Samuel Edward Konkin III]],<ref>Konkin III, Samuel Edward. ''[http://agorism.info/docs/NewLibertarianManifesto.pdf The New Libertarian Manifesto]''.</ref> Sheldon Richman,<ref name="LibertarianLeft"/><ref>Richman, Sheldon (18 December 2009). [http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/tgif/workers-of-the-world-unite "Workers of the World Unite for a Free Market"]. {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140722145233/http://www.thefreemanonline.org/columns/tgif/workers-of-the-world-unite|date=22 July 2014}}. Foundation for Economic Education.</ref><ref name="LibertarianLeft"/> [[Chris Matthew Sciabarra]]<ref>Sciabarra, Chris Matthew (2000). ''Total Freedom: Toward a Dialectical Libertarianism''. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.</ref> and [[Gary Chartier]],<ref>Chartier, Gary (2009). ''Economic Justice and Natural Law''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.</ref> who stress the value of radically free markets, termed [[freed market]]s to distinguish them from the common conception which these libertarians believe to be riddled with statist and capitalist privileges.<ref name="marketsnotcap">Gillis, William (2011). "The Freed Market". In Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. ''Markets Not Capitalism''. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 19–20.</ref> Referred to as left-wing market anarchists<ref>Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). ''Markets Not Capitalism''. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 1–16.</ref> or market-oriented left-libertarians,<ref name="LibertarianLeft"/> proponents of this approach strongly affirm the [[classical liberal]] ideas of [[self-ownership]] and [[free markets]] while maintaining that taken to their logical conclusions these ideas support strongly [[anti-capitalist]], [[Anti-corporatism|anti-corporatist]], anti-[[hierarchical]] and [[pro-labor]] positions in economics; [[anti-imperialism]] in foreign policy; and thoroughly [[Cultural liberalism|liberal]] or [[Civil libertarianism|radical]] views regarding cultural issues as such as gender, sexuality and race. This strand of left-libertarianism tends to be rooted either in the [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualist economics]] conceptualized by [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], [[American individualist anarchism]], or in a [[left-wing]] interpretation or extension of the thought of [[Murray Rothbard]]. According to libertarian scholar Sheldon Richman: {{quote|Left-libertarians favor worker solidarity vis-à-vis bosses, support poor people's [[squatting]] on government or abandoned property, and prefer that corporate privileges be repealed before the regulatory restrictions on how those privileges may be exercised. They see [[Walmart]] as a symbol of corporate favoritism—supported by highway subsidies and eminent domain—view the fictive personhood of the [[Limited liability company|limited-liability corporation]] with suspicion, and doubt that [[Third World]] [[sweatshop]]s would be the "best alternative" in the absence of government manipulation. Left-libertarians tend to eschew electoral politics, having little confidence in strategies that work through the government. They prefer to develop alternative institutions and methods of working around the state.<ref name="LibertarianLeft"/>}}


[[Gary Chartier]] has joined [[Kevin Carson]], Charles W. Johnson and others (echoing the language of [[Stephen Pearl Andrews]], [[William Batchelder Greene]], [[Thomas Hodgskin]], [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], [[Lysander Spooner]], [[Benjamin Tucker]] and [[Josiah Warren]], among others) in maintaining that because of its heritage and its emancipatory goals and potential radical market anarchism should be seen by its proponents and by others as part of the socialist tradition and that market anarchists can and should call themselves socialists.<ref name="c4ss.org">Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose Capitalism," "Free-Market Anti-Capitalism?" session, annual conference, [[Association of Private Enterprise Education]] (Cæsar's Palace, Las Vegas, NV, April 13, 2010); Gary Chartier, [http://c4ss.org/content/1738 "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Embrace 'Anti-Capitalism'"]; Gary Chartier, [http://invisiblemolotov.wordpress.com/2009/09/12/socialist-ends-market-means/ ''Socialist Ends, Market Means: Five Essays'']. Cp. Tucker, "Socialism".</ref>
[[Gary Chartier]] has joined [[Kevin Carson]], Charles W. Johnson and others (echoing the language of [[Stephen Pearl Andrews]], [[William Batchelder Greene]], [[Thomas Hodgskin]], [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], [[Lysander Spooner]], [[Benjamin Tucker]] and [[Josiah Warren]], among others) in maintaining that because of its heritage and its emancipatory goals and potential radical market anarchism should be seen by its proponents and by others as part of the socialist tradition and that market anarchists can and should call themselves socialists.<ref name="c4ss.org">Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose Capitalism," "Free-Market Anti-Capitalism?" session, annual conference, [[Association of Private Enterprise Education]] (Cæsar's Palace, Las Vegas, NV, April 13, 2010); Gary Chartier, [http://c4ss.org/content/1738 "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Embrace 'Anti-Capitalism'"]; Gary Chartier, [http://invisiblemolotov.wordpress.com/2009/09/12/socialist-ends-market-means/ ''Socialist Ends, Market Means: Five Essays'']. Cp. Tucker, "Socialism".</ref>
Line 36: Line 53:


The genealogy of contemporary market-oriented left-libertarianism, sometimes labeled left-wing market anarchism,<ref>Chris Sciabarra is the only scholar associated with this school of left-libertarianism who is skeptical about anarchism. See Sciabarra's ''Total Freedom''.</ref> overlaps to a significant degree with that of Steiner–Vallentyne left-libertarianism as the roots of that tradition are sketched in ''The Origins of Left-Libertarianism''. Carson–Long-style left-libertarianism is rooted in 19th-century [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]] and in the work of figures such as the British [[Thomas Hodgskin]] and the American [[individualist anarchist]]s [[Benjamin Tucker]] and [[Lysander Spooner]]. While with notable exceptions market-oriented libertarians after Tucker tended to ally with the [[political right]], relationships between such libertarians and the [[New Left]] thrived in the 1960s, laying the groundwork for modern left-wing market anarchism.<ref>Long, Roderick T. (2006). "[https://mises.org/daily/2099 Rothbard's 'Left and Right': Forty Years Later]." Rothbard Memorial Lecture, Austrian Scholars Conference.</ref>
The genealogy of contemporary market-oriented left-libertarianism, sometimes labeled left-wing market anarchism,<ref>Chris Sciabarra is the only scholar associated with this school of left-libertarianism who is skeptical about anarchism. See Sciabarra's ''Total Freedom''.</ref> overlaps to a significant degree with that of Steiner–Vallentyne left-libertarianism as the roots of that tradition are sketched in ''The Origins of Left-Libertarianism''. Carson–Long-style left-libertarianism is rooted in 19th-century [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]] and in the work of figures such as the British [[Thomas Hodgskin]] and the American [[individualist anarchist]]s [[Benjamin Tucker]] and [[Lysander Spooner]]. While with notable exceptions market-oriented libertarians after Tucker tended to ally with the [[political right]], relationships between such libertarians and the [[New Left]] thrived in the 1960s, laying the groundwork for modern left-wing market anarchism.<ref>Long, Roderick T. (2006). "[https://mises.org/daily/2099 Rothbard's 'Left and Right': Forty Years Later]." Rothbard Memorial Lecture, Austrian Scholars Conference.</ref>

=== Internal disputes and views on property ===
[[File:BenjaminTucker.jpg|thumb|[[American individualist anarchist]] [[Benjamin Tucker]], known for his [[libertarian]] journal ''[[Liberty (1881–1908)|Liberty]]'', abandoned the [[natural rights]] conception of [[property rights]] in free-market anarchism for a [[Philosophy of Max Stirner|Stirnerite]] [[Egoist anarchism|egoism]]]]
[[Murray Rothbard]] and other [[natural rights]] theorists cite the [[non-aggression axiom]] as the basis for their libertarian systems while other free-market anarchists such as [[David D. Friedman]] favor free-market anarchism based on [[consequentialist]] ethical theories.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Danley|first=John R.|url=https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/BF00383797|date=November 1991|title=Polestar refined: Business ethics and political economy|journal=[[Journal of Business Ethics]]|publisher=Springer Netherlands|volume=10|issue=12|pages=915–933|doi=10.1007/BF00383797|accessdate=15 July 2019}}</ref> [[Voluntaryism|Voluntarists]], [[Paleolibertarianism|paleolibertarians]] and [[Agorism|agorists]] are [[propertarian]] market anarchists who consider private [[property right]]s to be individual [[natural right]]s deriving from the primary right of [[self-ownership]]. Market anarchists state diverse views concerning the path to elimination of the state. Rothbard endorses the use of any tactic to bring about market anarchy so long as it does not contradict his libertarian moral principles.<ref>Lora, Ronald; Longton, Henry (1999). ''The Conservative Press in Twentieth-Century America''. Greenwood Press. p. 369.</ref>

==== Tuckerites ====
[[Benjamin Tucker]] originally subscribed to the idea of land ownership associated with [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]] which does not grant that this creates property in land, but rather holds that when people customarily use given land and in some versions goods other people should respect that use or [[Ownership|possession]]. Unlike with [[property]], ownership is no longer recognized when that use stops.<ref>Swartz, Clarence Lee. ''What Is Mutualism?''. [http://www.panarchy.org/swartz/mutualism.6.html "VI. Land and Rent"].</ref> The mutualist theory holds that the stopping of use or occupying land reverts it to the commons or to an unowned condition, and makes it available for anyone that wishes to use it.<ref>Carson, Kevin. ''Studies in Mutualist Political Economy''. Chapter 5.</ref><ref>Long, Roderick T. "Land-Locked: A Critique of Carson on Property Rights". ''[[Journal of Libertarian Studies]]''. '''20''' (1).</ref> As a result, there would be no market in land that is not in use. However, Tucker later abandoned natural rights theory and said that land ownership is legitimately transferred through force unless specified otherwise by contracts: "Man's only right to land is his might over it. If his neighbor is mightier than he and takes the land from him, then the land is his neighbor's, until the latter is dispossessed by one mightier still".<ref>Tucker, Benjamin (31 December 1892). "Response to 'Rights,' by William Hansen". ''Liberty''. '''9''' (18): 1.</ref> He expected that individuals would come to the realization that the "occupancy and use" was a "generally trustworthy guiding principle of action" and that individuals would likely contract to an occupancy and use policy.<ref>Tucker, Benjamin (6 April 1895). "The Two Conceptions of Equal Freedom". ''Liberty''. '''10''' (24): 4.</ref>

==== Rothbardians ====
[[File:Murray Rothbard.jpg|thumb|left|[[Murray Rothbard]] asserted that "capitalism is the fullest expression of anarchism, and anarchism is the fullest expression of capitalism"<ref>[http://archive.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard103.html "Exclusive Interview With Murray Rothbard"]. ''The New Banner: A Fortnightly Libertarian Journal''. 25 February 1972.</ref>]]
[[Classical liberal]] [[John Locke]] argues that as people apply their labor to unowned resources, they make those resources their [[property]]. For Locke, there are only two legitimate ways people can acquire new property, namely by mixing their labor with unowned resources or by voluntary trade for created goods. In accordance with Locke's philosophy, Rothbardian free-market anarchists believe that property may only originate by being the product of labor and that its ownership may only legitimately change as a result of exchange or gift. They derive this [[homestead principle]] from what they call the principle of [[self-ownership]].<ref name="propertyrights"/><ref name="propertyownership"/> Locke had a [[Lockean proviso|proviso]] which says that the appropriator of resources must leave "enough and as good in common to others", but [[Murray Rothbard]]'s market anarchist followers do not agree with this proviso, believing instead that the individual may [[Original appropriation|originally appropriate]] as much as she wishes through the application of her labor and that property thus acquired remains hers until she chooses otherwise,<ref name="propertyrights">{{cite journal |title=Land-locked: A Critique of Carson on Property Rights |last=Long |first=Roderick T. |authorlink=Roderick T. Long |volume=20 |issue=1 |year=2006 |pages=87–95 |journal=[[Journal of Libertarian Studies]] |url=https://mises.org/journals/jls/20_1/20_1_6.pdf}}</ref><ref name="propertyownership">{{cite journal |title=Man and Matter: A Philosophical Inquiry into the Justification of Ownership in Land from the Basis of Self-Ownership |last=Bylund |first=Per |url=http://www.perbylund.com/academics_polsci_msc.pdf}}</ref> terming this as neo-Lockean.<ref name="propertyownership"/><ref name="verhaegh">{{cite journal |last=Verhaegh |first=Marcus |year=2006 |title=Rothbard as a Political Philosopher |url=https://mises.org/journals/jls/20_4/20_4_1.pdf |journal=[[Journal of Libertarian Studies]] |volume=20 |issue=4 |page=3 }}</ref>

[[Anarcho-capitalism|Anarcho-capitalists]] see this as consistent with their opposition to initiatory coercion since only land which is not already owned can be taken without compensation. If something is unowned, there is no person against whom the original appropriator is initiating coercion. They do not think that a claim of and by itself can create ownership, but rather that the application of one's labor to the unowned object as for example beginning to farm unowned land. They accept voluntary forms of [[common ownership]], which means property open to all individuals to access.<ref name="commonproperty">{{cite journal |title=Common Property in Anarcho-Capitalism |last=Holcombe |first=Randall G. |authorlink=Randall G. Holcombe |volume=19 |issue=2 |year=2005 |pages=3–29 |journal=[[Journal of Libertarian Studies]] |url=https://www.mises.org/journals/jls/19_2/19_2_1.pdf}}</ref> [[Samuel Edward Konkin III]], the founder of [[agorism]], was also a Rothbardian.<ref name="inter">[http://www.spaz.org/~dan/individualist-anarchist/software/konkin-interview.html "Smashing the State for Fun and Profit Since 1969: An Interview With the Libertarian Icon Samuel Edward Konkin III (a.k.a. SEK3)"].</ref>

Although anarcho-capitalism has been regarded by some as a form of [[individualist anarchism]],<ref name="marx">{{cite book |last=Bottomore |first=Tom |chapter=Anarchism |page=21 |title=A Dictionary of Marxist Thought |publisher=Blackwell Reference |location= Oxford | year = 1991 |isbn=0-63118082-6}}</ref><ref name="accounts">See the following sources:
* Alan and Trombley, Stephen (Eds.) Bullock, ''The Norton Dictionary of Modern Thought'', W. W. Norton & Co (1999), p. 30.
* Barry, Norman. ''Modern Political Theory'', 2000, Palgrave, p. 70.
* Adams, Ian. ''Political Ideology Today'', Manchester University Press (2002) {{ISBN|0-7190-6020-6}}, p. 135.
* Grant, Moyra. ''Key Ideas in Politics'', Nelson Thomas 2003 {{ISBN|0-7487-7096-8}}, p. 91.
* Heider, Ulrike. ''Anarchism: Left, Right, and Green'', City Lights, 1994. p. 3.
* [[Paul Avrich|Avrich, Paul]]. ''[[Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in America]]'', Abridged Paperback Edition (1996), p. 282.
* Tormey, Simon. ''Anti-Capitalism'', One World, 2004. pp. 118–19.
* [[Ralph Raico|Raico, Ralph]]. ''Authentic German Liberalism of the 19th Century'', École Polytechnique, Centre de Recherche en Épistémologie Appliquée, Unité associée au CNRS, 2004.
* Busky, Donald. Democratic Socialism: A Global Survey, Praeger/Greenwood (2000), p. 4.
* Heywood, Andrew. Politics: Second Edition, Palgrave (2002), p. 61.
* Offer, John. ''Herbert Spencer: Critical Assessments'', Routledge (UK) (2000), p. 243.</ref> Rothbard stated that individualist anarchism is different from [[capitalism]] due to the individualist anarchists retaining the [[labor theory of value]]<ref name="Are Libertarians 'Anarchists'">Rothbard, Murray. [http://archive.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard167.html Are Libertarians 'Anarchists'?]. ''LewRockwell.com''.</ref> and many writers [[Issues in anarchism#Capitalism|deny that anarcho-capitalism is a form of anarchism at all]],<ref>See the following sources:
* K, David. "What is Anarchism?" Bastard Press (2005).
* Marshall, Peter. Demanding the Impossible, London: Fontana Press, 1992 ({{ISBN|0-00-686245-4}}) Chapter 38.
* MacSaorsa, Iain. "Is 'anarcho' capitalism against the state?" Spunk Press (archive).
* Wells, Sam. "Anarcho-Capitalism is Not Anarchism, and Political Competition is Not Economic Competition" Frontlines 1 (January 1979).</ref> or that [[Anarchism and capitalism|capitalism itself is compatible with anarchism]].<ref>See the following sources:
* Peikoff, Leonard. 'Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand' Dutton Adult (1991) Chapter "Government".
* Doyle, Kevin. 'Crypto Anarchy, Cyberstates, and Pirate Utopias' New York: Lexington Books, (2002) pp. 447–48.
* Sheehan, Seán M. 'Anarchism' Reaktion Books, 2003 p. 17.
* Kelsen, Hans. The Communist Theory of Law. Wm. S. Hein Publishing (1988) p. 110.
* Egbert. Tellegen, Maarten. Wolsink 'Society and Its Environment: an introduction' Routledge (1998) p. 64.
* Jones, James 'The Merry Month of May' Akashic Books (2004) pp. 37–38.
* Sparks, Chris. Isaacs, Stuart 'Political Theorists in Context' Routledge (2004) p. 238.
* Bookchin, Murray. 'Post-Scarcity Anarchism' AK Press (2004) p. 37.
* Berkman, Alexander. 'Life of an Anarchist' Seven Stories Press (2005) p. 268.</ref>


== Criticism ==
== Criticism ==

Revision as of 03:24, 13 November 2019

Free-market anarchism,[1] also known as free-market anti-capitalism[2] and free-market socialism,[3] is a branch of anarchism that advocate a free-market economic system based on voluntary interactions without the involvement of the state. A form of individualist anarchism,[4] left-libertarianism[2] and libertarian socialism,[3][5] it is based on the economic theories of mutualism and 19th-century American individualist anarchism. One branch of market anarchism is left-wing market anarchism, including modern mutualists such as Kevin Carson and Gary Chartier, who consider themselves anti-capitalists and identify as part of the socialist movement.[6][7][8][9]

Samuel Edward Konkin III's agorism is a strand of left-wing market anarchism and has been associated with left-libertarianism in the United States,[10][11][12] with counter-economics being its means.[13] Anarcho-capitalism stresses the legitimacy and priority of private property, describing it as an integral component of individual rights and a free-market economy. However, there is a strong current within anarchism which does not consider anarcho-capitalism as part of the anarchist movement because anarchism has historically been an anti-capitalist movement and for definitional reasons which see anarchism incompatible with capitalist forms.[14][15][16][17][18][19]

As a result, the term may be used to refer to diverse economic and political concepts such as those proposed by individualist anarchists and libertarian socialists like the Europeans Thomas Hodgskin and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, or the Americans Stephen Pearl Andrews, William Batchelder Greene, Lysander Spooner, Benjamin Tucker and Josiah Warren, among others;[20][21] and alternatively anarcho-capitalists like Murray Rothbard[22] and David D. Friedman,[23] or anti-capitalists like Konkin,[11][24] Carson,[25][26][27] Chartier,[28][29] Roderick T. Long,[30][31] Charles W. Johnson,[32] Brad Spangler,[33] Sheldon Richman[34][35][2] and Chris Matthew Sciabarra.[36]

History

Mutualism

Josiah Warren, the first American anarchist, was an early mutualist

Josiah Warren is widely regarded as the first American anarchist[37] and the four-page weekly paper he edited during 1833, The Peaceful Revolutionist, was the first anarchist periodical published,[38] an enterprise for which he built his own printing press, cast his own type and made his own printing plates.[38] Warren was a follower of Robert Owen and joined Owen's community at New Harmony, Indiana. Josiah Warren termed the phrase "cost the limit of price", with "cost" here referring not to monetary price paid but the labor one exerted to produce an item.[39] Therefore, "he proposed a system to pay people with certificates indicating how many hours of work they did. They could exchange the notes at local time stores for goods that took the same amount of time to produce".[37] He put his theories to the test by establishing an experimental "labor for labor store" called the Cincinnati Time Store where trade was facilitated by notes backed by a promise to perform labor. The store proved successful and operated for three years after which it was closed so that Warren could pursue establishing colonies based on mutualism. These included Utopia and Modern Times. Warren said that Stephen Pearl Andrews' The Science of Society, published in 1852, was the most lucid and complete exposition of Warren's own theories.[40] Catalan historian Xavier Diez report that the intentional communal experiments pioneered by Warren were influential in European individualist anarchists of the late 19th and early 20th centuries such as Emile Armand and the intentional communities started by them.[41]

Mutualism began in 18th-century English and French labour movements before taking an anarchist form associated with Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in France and others in the United States.[42] Proudhon proposed spontaneous order, whereby organisation emerges without central authority, a "positive anarchy" where order arises when everybody does "what he wishes and only what he wishes"[43] and where "business transactions alone produce the social order".[44] It is important to recognize that Proudhon distinguished between ideal political possibilities and practical governance. For this reason, much in contrast to some of his theoretical statements concerning ultimate spontaneous self-governance, Proudhon was heavily involved in French parliamentary politics and allied himself not with Anarchist but Socialist factions of workers movements and in addition to advocating state-protected charters for worker-owned cooperatives, promoted certain nationalization schemes during his life of public service. Mutualist anarchism is concerned with reciprocity, free association, voluntary contract, federation and credit and currency reform. According to the American mutualist William Batchelder Greene, each worker in the mutualist system would receive "just and exact pay for his work; services equivalent in cost being exchangeable for services equivalent in cost, without profit or discount".[45] Mutualism has been retrospectively characterised as ideologically situated between individualist and collectivist forms of anarchism.[46] Proudhon first characterised his goal as a "third form of society, the synthesis of communism and property".[47]

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, the first self-identified anarchist, supported a left-wing market anarchism called mutualism

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon was a French activist and theorist, the founder of mutualist philosophy, an economist and a libertarian socialist. He was the first person to declare himself an anarchist[48] and is among its most influential theorists. He is considered by many to be the "father of anarchism".[49] He became a member of the French Parliament after the Revolution of 1848, whereupon and thereafter he referred to himself as a federalist.[50] Proudhon, who was born in Besançon, was a printer who taught himself Latin in order to better print books in the language. His best-known assertion is that Property is Theft!, contained in his first major work, What is Property? Or, an Inquiry into the Principle of Right and Government (Qu'est-ce que la propriété? Recherche sur le principe du droit et du gouvernement), published in 1840. The book's publication attracted the attention of the French authorities. It also attracted the scrutiny of Karl Marx, who started a correspondence with its author. The two influenced each other: they met in Paris while Marx was exiled there. Their friendship finally ended when Marx responded to Proudhon's The System of Economic Contradictions, or The Philosophy of Poverty with the provocatively titled The Poverty of Philosophy. The dispute became one of the sources of the split between the anarchist and Marxian wings of the International Working Men's Association. Some, such as Edmund Wilson, have contended that Marx's attack on Proudhon had its origin in the latter's defense of Karl Grün, whom Marx bitterly disliked but who had been preparing translations of Proudhon's work. Proudhon favored workers' associations or co-operatives as well as individual worker/peasant possession over private ownership or the nationalization of land and workplaces. He considered social revolution to be achievable in a peaceful manner. In The Confessions of a Revolutionary Proudhon asserted that, Anarchy is Order Without Power, the phrase which much later inspired, in the view of some, the anarchist circled-A symbol, today "one of the most common graffiti on the urban landscape".[51] He unsuccessfully tried to create a national bank to be funded by what became an abortive attempt at an income tax on capitalists and shareholders. Similar in some respects to a credit union, it would have given interest-free loans.[52]

William Batchelder Greene was a 19th-century mutualist individualist anarchist, Unitarian minister, soldier and promoter of free banking in the United States. Greene is best known for the works Mutual Banking(1850), which proposed an interest-free banking system, and Transcendentalism, a critique of the New England philosophical school. American anarchist historian Eunice Minette Schuster states: "It is apparent that Proudhonian Anarchism was to be found in the United States at least as early as 1848 and that it was not conscious of its affinity to the Individualist Anarchism of Josiah Warren and Stephen Pearl Andrews. William B. Greene presented this Proudhonian Mutualism in its purest and most systematic form".[53] After 1850, he became active in labor reform[53] and was elected vice-president of the New England Labor Reform League, the majority of the members holding to Proudhon's scheme of mutual banking. In 1869, he was elected president of the Massachusetts Labor Union.[53] Greene then published Socialistic, Mutualistic, and Financial Fragments (1875).[53] He saw mutualism as the synthesis of "liberty and order".[53] His "associationism is checked by individualism. 'Mind your own business,' "Judge not that ye be not judged". Over matters which are purely personal, as for example moral conduct, the individual is sovereign, as well as over that which he himself produces. For this reason he demands "mutuality" in marriage – the equal right of a woman to her own personal freedom and property".[53]

Individualist anarchism in the United States

American individualist anarchist Benjamin Tucker, known for his libertarian journal Liberty, abandoned the natural rights conception of property rights in free-market anarchism for a Stirnerite egoism

A form of individualist anarchism was found in the United States as advocated by the Boston anarchists.[54] Some Boston anarchists, including Benjamin Tucker and Lysander Spooner, identified themselves as socialists, a term often used in the 19th century in the sense of a commitment to improving conditions of the working class (i.e. the labor problem).[55] The Boston anarchists such as Tucker and his followers are also considered socialists due to their opposition to usury.[56][57] By around the start of the 20th century, the heyday of individualist anarchism had passed,[58] On the other hand, anarchist historian George Woodcock describes Spooner's essays as an "eloquent elaboration" of Josiah Warren and the early American development of Proudhon's ideas and associates his works with that of Stephen Pearl Andrews.[59] Woodcock also reports that both Spooner and Greene had been members of the socialist First International.[60]

American individualist anarchist Benjamin Tucker identified as a socialist[61] and argued that the elimination of what he called the four monopolies, namely the land monopoly, the money and banking monopoly, the monopoly powers conferred by patents and the quasi-monopolistic effects of tariffs, would undermine the power of the wealthy and big business, making possible widespread property ownership and higher incomes for ordinary people, while minimizing the power of would-be bosses and achieving socialist goals without state action. Tucker influenced and interacted with anarchist contemporaries, including Spooner, Voltairine de Cleyre, Dyer D. Lum, and William B. Greene, who have in various ways influenced later left-libertarian thinking.[62] Kevin Carson characterizes American individualist anarchism by saying: "Unlike the rest of the socialist movement, the individualist anarchists believed that the natural wage of labor in a free market was its product and that economic exploitation could only take place when capitalists and landlords harnessed the power of the state in their interests. Thus, individualist anarchism was an alternative both to the increasing statism of the mainstream socialist movement and to a liberal movement that was moving toward a mere apologetic for the power of big business.[63] Two individualist anarchists who wrote in Benjamin Tucker's Liberty were also important labor organizers of the time. Joseph Labadie and Dyer Lum. Kevin Carson has praised Dyer Lum's fusion of individualist laissez-faire economics with radical labor activism as "creative" and described him as "more significant than any in the Boston group".[64]

Some of the American individualist anarchists later in this era such as Benjamin Tucker abandoned natural rights positions and converted to Max Stirner's egoist anarchism. Rejecting the idea of moral rights, Tucker said that there were only two rights, "the right of might" and "the right of contract". He also said after converting to egoist individualism: "In times past it was my habit to talk glibly of the right of man to land. It was a bad habit, and I long ago sloughed it off. Man's only right to land is his might over it".[65] In adopting Stirnerite egoism in 1886, Tucker rejected natural rights which had long been considered the foundation of libertarianism. This rejection galvanized the movement into fierce debates, with the natural rights proponents accusing the egoists of destroying libertarianism itself. So bitter was the conflict that a number of natural rights proponents withdrew from the pages of Liberty in protest even though they had hitherto been among its frequent contributors. Thereafter, Liberty championed egoism although its general content did not change significantly.[66]

Geolibertarianism

Henry George, whose economic positions known as geoism existed within European individualist anarchism

Geolibertarianism, an anarchist form of Henry George's philosophy called geoism, is considered left-libertarian because it assumes land to be initially owned in common, so that when land is privately appropriated the proprietor pays rent to the community.[67] Geolibertarians generally advocate distributing the land rent to the community via a land value tax as proposed by Henry George and others before him. For this reason, they are often called "single taxers". Fred E. Foldvary coined the word geo-libertarianism in an article so titled in Land and Liberty.[68] In the case of geoanarchism, the voluntary form of geolibertarianism as described by Foldvary, rent would be collected by private associations with the opportunity to secede from the rent-sharing community and not receive the community's services.[69]

Similar economic positions also existed within European individualist anarchism. French individualist anarchist Émile Armand shows clearly opposition to capitalism and centralized economies when he said that the individualist anarchist "inwardly he remains refractory – fatally refractory – morally, intellectually, economically (The capitalist economy and the directed economy, the speculators and the fabricators of single are equally repugnant to him.)".[70] He argued for a pluralistic economic logic when he said: "Here and there everything happening – here everyone receiving what they need, there each one getting whatever is needed according to their own capacity. Here, gift and barter – one product for another; there, exchange – product for representative value. Here, the producer is the owner of the product, there, the product is put to the possession of the collectivity".[71]

Spanish individualist anarchist Miguel Gimenez Igualada thought that "capitalism is an effect of government; the disappearance of government means capitalism falls from its pedestal vertiginously. That which we call capitalism is not something else but a product of the State, within which the only thing that is being pushed forward is profit, good or badly acquired. And so to fight against capitalism is a pointless task, since be it State capitalism or Enterprise capitalism, as long as Government exists, exploiting capital will exist. The fight, but of consciousness, is against the State".[72] His view on class division and technocracy are as follows: "Since when no one works for another, the profiteer from wealth disappears, just as government will disappear when no one pays attention to those who learned four things at universities and from that fact they pretend to govern men. Big industrial enterprises will be transformed by men in big associations in which everyone will work and enjoy the product of their work. And from those easy as well as beautiful problems anarchism deals with and he who puts them in practice and lives them are anarchists. The priority which without rest an anarchist must make is that in which no one has to exploit anyone, no man to no man, since that non-exploitation will lead to the limitation of property to individual needs".[73]

Alliance between American libertarians and the New Left

The doyen of modern American market-oriented libertarianism, Austrian School economist Murray Rothbard, was initially an enthusiastic partisan of the Old Right, particularly because of its general opposition to war and imperialism.[74] However, Rothbard had long embraced a reading of American history that emphasized the role of elite privilege in shaping legal and political institutions—one that was naturally agreeable to many on the left—and came increasingly in the 1960s to seek alliances on the left—especially with members of the New Left—in light of the Vietnam War,[75] the military draft and the emergence of the Black Power movement.[76]

Working with other radicals like Ronald Radosh[77] and Karl Hess,[78] Rothbard argued that the consensus view of American economic history, according to which a beneficent government has used its power to counter corporate predation, is fundamentally flawed. Rather, he argued, government intervention in the economy has largely benefited established players at the expense of marginalized groups, to the detriment of both liberty and equality. Moreover, the robber baron period, hailed by the right and despised by the left as a heyday of laissez-faire, was not characterized by laissez-faire at all, but it was in fact a time of massive state privilege accorded to capital.[79] In tandem with his emphasis on the intimate connection between state and corporate power, he defended the seizure of corporations dependent on state largesse by workers and others.[80]

Rothbard himself ultimately broke with the left, allying himself instead with the burgeoning paleoconservative movement.[81] Drawing on the work of Rothbard during his alliance with the left and on the thought of Karl Hess, some thinkers associated with market-oriented American libertarianism came increasingly to identify with the left on a range of issues, including opposition to war, to corporate oligopolies and to state-corporate partnerships as well as an affinity for cultural liberalism. One variety of this kind of libertarianism has been a resurgent mutualism, incorporating modern economic ideas such as marginal utility theory into mutualist theory. Kevin Carson's Studies in Mutualist Political Economy[82] helped to stimulate the growth of new-style mutualism, articulating a version of the labor theory of value incorporating ideas drawn from Austrian economics.[83] Other market-oriented left-libertarians have declined to embrace mutualist views of real property while sharing the mutualist opposition to corporate hierarchies and wealth concentration.[84] Left-libertarians have placed particular emphasis on the articulation and defense of a libertarian theory of class and class conflict, although considerable work in this area has been performed by libertarians of other persuasions.[85]

Left-wing market anarchism

Left-wing market anarchism is a contemporary school of left-libertarianism and a revival of the free-market anarchist theories of mutualism and 19th century individualst anarchism. It is associated with scholars such as Kevin Carson,[86][87] Roderick T. Long,[88][89] Charles W. Johnson,[90] Samuel Edward Konkin III,[91] Sheldon Richman,[2][92][2] Chris Matthew Sciabarra[93] and Gary Chartier,[94] who stress the value of radically free markets, termed freed markets to distinguish them from the common conception which these libertarians believe to be riddled with statist and capitalist privileges.[95] Referred to as left-wing market anarchists[96] or market-oriented left-libertarians,[2] proponents of this approach strongly affirm the classical liberal ideas of self-ownership and free markets while maintaining that taken to their logical conclusions these ideas support strongly anti-capitalist, anti-corporatist, anti-hierarchical and pro-labor positions in economics; anti-imperialism in foreign policy; and thoroughly liberal or radical views regarding cultural issues as such as gender, sexuality and race. This strand of left-libertarianism tends to be rooted either in the mutualist economics conceptualized by Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, American individualist anarchism, or in a left-wing interpretation or extension of the thought of Murray Rothbard. According to libertarian scholar Sheldon Richman:

Left-libertarians favor worker solidarity vis-à-vis bosses, support poor people's squatting on government or abandoned property, and prefer that corporate privileges be repealed before the regulatory restrictions on how those privileges may be exercised. They see Walmart as a symbol of corporate favoritism—supported by highway subsidies and eminent domain—view the fictive personhood of the limited-liability corporation with suspicion, and doubt that Third World sweatshops would be the "best alternative" in the absence of government manipulation. Left-libertarians tend to eschew electoral politics, having little confidence in strategies that work through the government. They prefer to develop alternative institutions and methods of working around the state.[2]

Gary Chartier has joined Kevin Carson, Charles W. Johnson and others (echoing the language of Stephen Pearl Andrews, William Batchelder Greene, Thomas Hodgskin, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Lysander Spooner, Benjamin Tucker and Josiah Warren, among others) in maintaining that because of its heritage and its emancipatory goals and potential radical market anarchism should be seen by its proponents and by others as part of the socialist tradition and that market anarchists can and should call themselves socialists.[97]

Contemporary free-market left-libertarians also show markedly more sympathy than mainstream or paleolibertarians towards various cultural movements which challenge non-governmental relations of power. For instance, left-libertarians Roderick T. Long and Charles W. Johnson have called for a recovery of the 19th-century alliance with radical liberalism and feminism.[98] Forms of geolibertarianism also fit into this group, but these geoists are less likely to accept terms such as anti-capitalist or socialist. While adopting familiar libertarian views, including opposition to drug prohibition, gun control, civil liberties violations and war, left-libertarians are more likely than most self-identified libertarians to take more distinctively leftist stances on issues as diverse as feminism, gender and sexuality, class, immigration and environmentalism. Especially influential regarding these topics have been scholars including Long, Johnson, Chris Matthew Sciabarra and Arthur Silber.

The genealogy of contemporary market-oriented left-libertarianism, sometimes labeled left-wing market anarchism,[99] overlaps to a significant degree with that of Steiner–Vallentyne left-libertarianism as the roots of that tradition are sketched in The Origins of Left-Libertarianism. Carson–Long-style left-libertarianism is rooted in 19th-century mutualism and in the work of figures such as the British Thomas Hodgskin and the American individualist anarchists Benjamin Tucker and Lysander Spooner. While with notable exceptions market-oriented libertarians after Tucker tended to ally with the political right, relationships between such libertarians and the New Left thrived in the 1960s, laying the groundwork for modern left-wing market anarchism.[100]

Criticism

A well-known criticism of free-market anarchism is by Robert Nozick, who argued that a competitive legal system would evolve toward a monopoly government—even without violating individuals rights in the process.[101] While free-market anarchists such as Roy Childs and Murray Rothbard have rejected Nozick's arguments,[102] John Jefferson actually advocates Nozick's argument and states that such events would best operate in laissez-faire.[103]

See also

References

  1. ^ Hoffman, John; Graham, Paul (2006). Introduction to Political Theory. p. 243.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g Sheldon Richman (3 February 2011). "Libertarian Left: Free-market anti-capitalism, the unknown ideal". The American Conservative. Retrieved 5 March 2012.
  3. ^ a b Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). Markets Not Capitalism: Individualist Anarchism Against Bosses, Inequality, Corporate Power, and Structural Poverty. Brooklyn: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. p. back cover. "It introduces an eye-opening approach to radical social thought, rooted equally in libertarian socialism and market anarchism."
  4. ^ Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). Markets Not Capitalism: Individualist Anarchism Against Bosses, Inequality, Corporate Power, and Structural Poverty. Brooklyn: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia.
  5. ^ Carson, Kevin. "Socialism: A Perfectly Good Word Rehabilitated". Center for a Stateless Society. "But there has always been a market-oriented strand of libertarian socialism that emphasizes voluntary cooperation between producers. And markets, properly understood, have always been about cooperation. As a commenter at Reason magazine's Hit&Run blog, remarking on Jesse Walker's link to the Kelly article, put it: "every trade is a cooperative act." In fact, it's a fairly common observation among market anarchists that genuinely free markets have the most legitimate claim to the label "socialism."
  6. ^ Gary Chartier and Charles W. Johnson (eds). Markets Not Capitalism: Individualist Anarchism Against Bosses, Inequality, Corporate Power, and Structural Poverty. Minor Compositions; 1st edition November 5, 2011.
  7. ^ Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose Capitalism," "Free-Market Anti-Capitalism?" session, annual conference, Association of Private Enterprise Education (Cæsar's Palace, Las Vegas, NV, April 13, 2010)
  8. ^ Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Embrace 'Anti-Capitalism'".
  9. ^ Gary Chartier, Socialist Ends, Market Means: Five Essays. Cp. Tucker, "Socialism."
  10. ^ "Smashing the State for Fun and Profit Since 1969: An Interview With the Libertarian Icon Samuel Edward Konkin III (a.k.a. SEK3)".
  11. ^ a b D'Amato, David S. (27 November 2018). "Black-Market Activism: Samuel Edward Konkin III and Agorism".
  12. ^ Konkin III, Samuel Edward. An Agorist Primer (PDF).
  13. ^ "Counter-Economics: what it is, how it works" (PDF). Agorism.info. Archived from the original (PDF) on 25 March 2009.
  14. ^ Sabatini, Peter (Fall/Winter 1994–1995). "Libertarianism: Bogus Anarchy". Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed (41). "Within Libertarianism, Rothbard represents a minority perspective that actually argues for the total elimination of the state. However Rothbard's claim as an anarchist is quickly voided when it is shown that he only wants an end to the public state. In its place he allows countless private states, with each person supplying their own police force, army, and law, or else purchasing these services from capitalist venders...so what remains is shrill anti-statism conjoined to a vacuous freedom in hackneyed defense of capitalism. In sum, the "anarchy" of Libertarianism reduces to a liberal fraud".
  15. ^ Meltzer, Albert (2000). Anarchism: Arguments For and Against. AK Press. p. 50. "The philosophy of "anarcho-capitalism" dreamed up by the "libertarian" New Right, has nothing to do with Anarchism as known by the Anarchist movement proper".
  16. ^ Goodway, David (2006). Anarchist Seeds Beneath the Snow: Left-Libertarian Thought and British Writers from William Morris to Colin Ward. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press. p. 4. "'Libertarian' and 'libertarianism' are frequently employed by anarchists as synonyms for 'anarchist' and 'anarchism', largely as an attempt to distance themselves from the negative connotations of 'anarchy' and its derivatives. The situation has been vastly complicated in recent decades with the rise of anarcho-capitalism, 'minimal statism' and an extreme right-wing laissez-faire philosophy advocated by such theorists as Murray Rothbard and Robert Nozick and their adoption of the words 'libertarian' and 'libertarianism'. It has therefore now become necessary to distinguish between their right libertarianism and the left libertarianism of the anarchist tradition".
  17. ^ Marshall, Peter (2008). Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism. London: Harper Perennial. p. 565. "In fact, few anarchists would accept the 'anarcho-capitalists' into the anarchist camp since they do not share a concern for economic equality and social justice, Their self-interested, calculating market men would be incapable of practising voluntary co-operation and mutual aid. Anarcho-capitalists, even if they do reject the State, might therefore best be called right-wing libertarians rather than anarchists".
  18. ^ "Section F – Is "anarcho"-capitalism a type of anarchism?". An Anarchist FAQ (2008). Published in physical book form by "An Anarchist FAQ" as Volume I. Oakland/Edinburgh: AK Press. 558 pp. ISBN 9781902593906.
  19. ^ Newman, Saul (2010). The Politics of Postanarchism, Edinburgh University Press. p. 43. ISBN 0748634959. "It is important to distinguish between anarchism and certain strands of right-wing libertarianism which at times go by the same name (for example, Murray Rothbard's anarcho-capitalism)".
  20. ^ Woodcock, George (1962). Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements. Melbourne: Penguin.
  21. ^ McKay, Iain, ed. (2008). An Anarchist FAQ. Stirling: AK Press. ISBN 978-1-902593-90-6. OCLC 182529204.
  22. ^ Editor's note in "Taxation: Voluntary or Compulsory". Formulations. Free Nation Foundation. Summer 1995 "Taxation: Voluntary or Compulsory?". Archived from the original on 28 December 2010. Retrieved 15 March 2008.
  23. ^ Gerald F. Gaus, Chandran Kukathas. 2004. Handbook of Political Theory. Sage Publications. pp. 118–119. Source refers to Friedman's philosophy as "market anarchism."
  24. ^ Broze, Derrick (13 September 2016). "Agorism is Not Anarcho-Capitalism". Center for a Stateless Society. Retrieved 15 July 2019.
  25. ^ Carson, Kevin A. (2008). Organization Theory: A Libertarian Perspective. Charleston, SC: BookSurge.
  26. ^ Carson, Kevin (19 June 2009). "Socialism: A Perfectly Good Word Rehabilitated". Center for a Stateless Society. "But there has always been a market-oriented strand of libertarian socialism that emphasizes voluntary cooperation between producers. And markets, properly understood, have always been about cooperation. As a commenter at Reason magazine's Hit&Run blog, remarking on Jesse Walker's link to the Kelly article, put it: "every trade is a cooperative act." In fact, it's a fairly common observation among market anarchists that genuinely free markets have the most legitimate claim to the label "socialism."
  27. ^ Carson, Kevin (2010). The Homebrew Industrial Revolution: A Low-Overhead Manifesto. Charleston, SC: BookSurge.
  28. ^ Chartier, Gary (2009). Economic Justice and Natural Law. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.
  29. ^ Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). Markets Not Capitalism: Individualist Anarchism Against Bosses, Inequality, Corporate Power, and Structural Poverty. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. "It introduces an eye-opening approach to radical social thought, rooted equally in libertarian socialism and market anarchism."
  30. ^ Long, Roderick T. (2000). Reason and Value: Aristotle versus Rand. Washington, D.C.: Objectivist Center.
  31. ^ Long, Roderick T. (2008). "An Interview With Roderick Long".
  32. ^ Johnson, Charles W. (2008). "Liberty, Equality, Solidarity: Toward a Dialectical Anarchism". Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country?. In Long, Roderick T.; Machan, Tibor. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 155–188.
  33. ^ Spangler, Brad (15 September 2006). "Market Anarchism as Stigmergic Socialism". Archived 10 May 2011 at archive.today.
  34. ^ Richman, Sheldon (23 June 2010). "Why Left-Libertarian?". The Freeman. Foundation for Economic Education.
  35. ^ Richman, Sheldon (18 December 2009). "Workers of the World Unite for a Free Market". Archived 22 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine. Foundation for Economic Education.
  36. ^ Sciabarra, Chris Matthew (2000). Total Freedom: Toward a Dialectical Libertarianism. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  37. ^ a b Palmer, Brian (2010-12-29) What do anarchists want from us?, Slate.com
  38. ^ a b William Bailie, "Archived copy" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2012-02-04. Retrieved 2013-06-17.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link) Josiah Warren: The First American Anarchist — A Sociological Study, Boston: Small, Maynard & Co., 1906, p. 20
  39. ^ "A watch has a cost and a value. The cost consists of the amount of labor bestowed on the mineral or natural wealth, in converting it into metals…". Warren, Josiah. Equitable Commerce
  40. ^ Charles A. Madison. "Anarchism in the United States". Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 6, No. 1. (Jan., 1945), p. 53
  41. ^ Xavier Diez. L'Anarquisme Individualista A Espanya 1923–1938 Archived 2011-07-21 at the Wayback Machine p. 42
  42. ^ "A member of a community," The Mutualist; this 1826 series criticised Robert Owen's proposals, and has been attributed to a dissident Owenite, possibly from the Friendly Association for Mutual Interests of Valley Forge; Wilbur, Shawn, 2006, "More from the 1826 "Mutualist"?".
  43. ^ Proudhon, Solution to the Social Problem, ed. H. Cohen (New York: Vanguard Press, 1927), p. 45.
  44. ^ Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph (1979). The Principle of Federation. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. ISBN 0-8020-5458-7. The notion of anarchy in politics is just as rational and positive as any other. It means that once industrial functions have taken over from political functions, then business transactions alone produce the social order.
  45. ^ "Communism versus Mutualism", Socialistic, Communistic, Mutualistic and Financial Fragments. (Boston: Lee & Shepard, 1875) William Batchelder Greene: "Under the mutual system, each individual will receive the just and exact pay for his work; services equivalent in cost being exchangeable for services equivalent in cost, without profit or discount; and so much as the individual laborer will then get over and above what he has earned will come to him as his share in the general prosperity of the community of which he is an individual member."
  46. ^ Avrich, Paul. Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in America, Princeton University Press 1996 ISBN 0-691-04494-5, p. 6
    Blackwell Encyclopaedia of Political Thought, Blackwell Publishing 1991 ISBN 0-631-17944-5, p. 11.
  47. ^ Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. What Is Property? Princeton, MA: Benjamin R. Tucker, 1876. p. 281.
  48. ^ The Dynamite Club, John M. Merriman, p. 42
  49. ^ Daniel Guerin, Anarchism: From Theory to Practice (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970).
  50. ^ Binkley, Robert C. Realism and Nationalism 1852–1871. Read Books. p. 118
  51. ^ Marshall, Peter. Demanding the Impossible. Fontana, London. 1993. p. 558
  52. ^ Martin, Henri, & Alger, Abby Langdon. A Popular History of France from the First Revolution to the Present Time. D. Estes and C.E. Lauria. p. 189
  53. ^ a b c d e f Native American Anarchism: A Study of Left-Wing American Individualism by Eunice Minette Schuster Archived 2016-02-13 at the Wayback Machine
  54. ^ Levy, Carl. "Anarchism". Microsoft Encarta Online Encyclopedia 2007. Archived 2009-10-31.
  55. ^ Brooks, Frank H. 1994. The Individualist Anarchists: An Anthology of Liberty (1881–1908). Transaction Publishers. p. 75.
  56. ^ "G.1.4 Why is the social context important in evaluating Individualist Anarchism?" in An Anarchist FAQArchived March 15, 2013, at the Wayback Machine
  57. ^ Stanford, Jim. Economics for Everyone: A Short Guide to the Economics of Capitalism. Ann Arbor: MI., Pluto Press. 2008. p. 36.
  58. ^ Avrich, Paul. 2006. Anarchist Voices: An Oral History of Anarchism in America. AK Press. p. 6.
  59. ^ Woodcock, G. (1962). Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements. Melbourne: Penguin. p. 434.
  60. ^ Woodcock, G. (1962). Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements. Melbourne: Penguin. p. 460.
  61. ^ Tucker, Benjamin (1897). "State Socialism and Anarchism: How Far They Agree and Wherein They Differ." Instead of a Book: By a Man Too Busy to Write One. New York
  62. ^ On the nineteenth-century American individualist anarchists, see James J. Martin, Men against the State: The Expositors of Individualist Anarchism in America (Colorado Springs, CO: Myles 1970).
  63. ^ Kevin Carson. Organization Theory: A Libertarian Perspective. BOOKSURGE. 2008. p. 1
  64. ^ Carson, Kevin. "May Day Thoughts: Individualist Anarchism and the Labor Movement". Mutualist Blog: Free Market Anti-Capitalism.
  65. ^ Tucker, Instead of a Book, p. 350
  66. ^ Wendy McElroy, "Benjamin Tucker, Individualism, & Liberty: Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order"
  67. ^ "Geoanarchism by Fred Foldvary". Anti-state.com. 2001-07-15. Retrieved 2013-03-26.
  68. ^ May/June 1981, pp. 53–55.
  69. ^ Foldvary, Fred E. (2001-07-15). "Geoanarchism". anti-state.com. Retrieved 2009-04-15.
  70. ^ ""Anarchist Individualism as a Life and Activity" by Emile Armand". Spaz.org. 2002-03-01. Retrieved 2013-10-11.
  71. ^ Émile Armand. Anarchist Individualism and Amorous Comradeship
  72. ^ "el capitalismo es sólo el efecto del gobierno; desaparecido el gobierno, el capitalismo cae de su pedestal vertiginosamente.... Lo que llamamos capitalismo no es otra cosa que el producto del Estado, dentro del cual lo único que se cultiva es la ganancia, bien o mal habida. Luchar, pues, contra el capitalismo es tarea inútil, porque sea Capitalismo de Estado o Capitalismo de Empresa, mientras el Gobierno exista, existirá el capital que explota. La lucha, pero de conciencias, es contra el Estado."Anarquismo by Miguel Gimenez Igualada
  73. ^ "¿La propiedad? ¡Bah! No es problema. Porque cuando nadie trabaje para nadie, el acaparador de la riqueza desaparece, como ha de desaparecer el gobierno cuando nadie haga caso a los que aprendieron cuatro cosas en las universidades y por ese sólo hecho pretenden gobernar a los hombres. Porque si en la tierra de los ciegos el tuerto es rey, en donde todos ven y juzgan y disciernen, el rey estorba. Y de lo que se trata es de que no haya reyes porque todos sean hombres. Las grandes empresas industriales las transformarán los hombres en grandes asociaciones donde todos trabajen y disfruten del producto de su trabajo. Y de esos tan sencillos como hermosos problemas trata el anarquismo y al que lo cumple y vive es al que se le llama anarquista...El hincapié que sin cansancio debe hacer el anarquista es el de que nadie debe explotar a nadie, ningún hombre a ningún hombre, porque esa no-explotación llevaría consigo la limitación de la propiedad a las necesidades individuales."Anarquismo by Miguel Gimenez Igualada
  74. ^ Raimond, Justin (2001). An Enemy of the State: The Life of Murray N. Rothbard. Amherst, NY: Prometheus.
  75. ^ Raimondo, pp. 151–209.
  76. ^ Doherty, Brian M. (2007). Radicals for Capitalism: A Freewheeling History of the Modern American Libertarian Movement. New York: Public Affairs. p. 338.
  77. ^ Rothbard; Murray; Radosh, Ronald, eds. (1972). A New History of Leviathan: Essays on the Rise of the American Corporate State. New York: Dutton.
  78. ^ Hess, Karl (1975). Dear America. New York: Morrow.
  79. ^ On partnerships between the state and big business and the role of big business in promoting regulation, see Kolko, Gabriel (1977). The Triumph of Conservatism: A Reinterpretation of American History, 1900–1916. New York: Free; Shaffer, Butler (2008). In Restraint of Trade: The Business Campaign Against Competition, 1918–1938. Auburn, AL: Mises Institute.
  80. ^ Rothbard, Murray (15 June 1969). "Confiscation and the Homestead Principle." Libertarian Forum. 1 (6): pp. 3–4.
  81. ^ Raimondo 277-8; Doherty 562-5.
  82. ^ Carson, Kevin. "Studies in Mutualist Political Economy". Archived 15 April 2011 at the Wayback Machine. Chs. 1–3.
  83. ^ See Kevin Carson's Studies in Mutualist Political Economy (Charleston, SC: BookSurge 2007). This book was the focus of a symposium in the Journal of Libertarian Studies.
  84. ^ See Long, Roderick T. (Winter 2006). "Land Locked: A Critique of Carson on Property Rights". Journal of Libertarian Studies. 20 (1): 87–95.
  85. ^ Richman, Sheldon (13 July 2007). "Class Struggle Rightly Conceived". The Goal Is Freedom. Foundation for Economic Education; Nock, Albert Jay (1935). Our Enemy, the State; Oppenheimer, Franz (1997). The State. San Francisco: Fox; Palmer, Tom G. (2009). "Classical Liberalism, Marxism, and the Conflict of Classes: The Classical Liberal Theory of Class Conflict". Realizing Freedom: Libertarian Theory, History, and Practice. Washington, D.C.: Cato Institute. pp. 255–276; Conger, Wally (2006). Agorist Class Theory: A Left Libertarian Approach to Class Conflict Analysis (PDF). Archived 4 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine; Kevin A. Carson, "Another Free-for-All: Libertarian Class Analysis, Organized Labor, Etc.," Mutualist Blog: Free-Market Anti-Capitalism (n.p., 26 January 2006); Walter E. Grinder and John Hagel, "Toward a Theory of State Capitalism: Ultimate Decision Making and Class Structure". Journal of Libertarian Studies 1.1 (1977): 59–79; David M. Hart, "The Radical Liberalism of Charles Comte and Charles Dunoyer" (PhD diss., U of Cambridge, 1994); Hans-Hermann Hoppe, "Marxist and Austrian Class Analysis". Journal of Libertarian Studies 9.2 (1990): 79–93; Long, Roderick T. "Toward a Libertarian Theory of Class". Social Philosophy and Policy 15.2 (Sum. 1998): 303–349.
  86. ^ Carson, Kevin A. (2008). Organization Theory: A Libertarian Perspective. Charleston, SC:BookSurge.
  87. ^ Carson, Kevin A. (2010). The Homebrew Industrial Revolution: A Low-Overhead Manifesto. Charleston, SC: BookSurge.
  88. ^ Long, Roderick T. (2000). Reason and Value: Aristotle versus Rand. Washington, D.C.: Objectivist Center
  89. ^ Long, Roderick T. (2008). "An Interview With Roderick Long".
  90. ^ Johnson, Charles W. (2008). "Liberty, Equality, Solidarity: Toward a Dialectical Anarchism". Anarchism/Minarchism: Is a Government Part of a Free Country?. In Long, Roderick T.; Machan, Tibor. Aldershot: Ashgate pp. 155–188.
  91. ^ Konkin III, Samuel Edward. The New Libertarian Manifesto.
  92. ^ Richman, Sheldon (18 December 2009). "Workers of the World Unite for a Free Market". Archived 22 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine. Foundation for Economic Education.
  93. ^ Sciabarra, Chris Matthew (2000). Total Freedom: Toward a Dialectical Libertarianism. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
  94. ^ Chartier, Gary (2009). Economic Justice and Natural Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  95. ^ Gillis, William (2011). "The Freed Market". In Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. Markets Not Capitalism. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 19–20.
  96. ^ Chartier, Gary; Johnson, Charles W. (2011). Markets Not Capitalism. Brooklyn, NY: Minor Compositions/Autonomedia. pp. 1–16.
  97. ^ Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose Capitalism," "Free-Market Anti-Capitalism?" session, annual conference, Association of Private Enterprise Education (Cæsar's Palace, Las Vegas, NV, April 13, 2010); Gary Chartier, "Advocates of Freed Markets Should Embrace 'Anti-Capitalism'"; Gary Chartier, Socialist Ends, Market Means: Five Essays. Cp. Tucker, "Socialism".
  98. ^ Long, Roderick T.; Johnson, Charles W. (1 May 2005). "Libertarian Feminism: Can this Marriage Be Saved?" Molinari Society.
  99. ^ Chris Sciabarra is the only scholar associated with this school of left-libertarianism who is skeptical about anarchism. See Sciabarra's Total Freedom.
  100. ^ Long, Roderick T. (2006). "Rothbard's 'Left and Right': Forty Years Later." Rothbard Memorial Lecture, Austrian Scholars Conference.
  101. ^ Jeffrey Paul, Fred Dycus Miller. Liberalism and the economic order. Cambridge University Press, 1993, p. 115.
  102. ^ See Childs's incomplete essay, "Anarchist Illusions", Liberty against Power: Essays by Roy A. Childs, Jr., ed. Joan Kennedy Taylor (San Francisco: Fox 1994) 179–183.
  103. ^ Jeffrey Paul, Fred Dycus Miller. Liberalism and the economic order. Cambridge University Press, 1993, p. 118.